-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 21
/
Copy pathSunk cost.page
601 lines (414 loc) · 164 KB
/
Sunk cost.page
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
---
title: Are Sunk Costs Fallacies?
description: human and animal sunk costs often aren't, and sunk cost bias may be useful
created: 24 Jan 2012
tags: psychology, philosophy
status: finished
belief: likely
...
> "It is time to let bygones be bygones" --[Khieu Samphan](!Wikipedia)^[["World: Asia-Pacific: US demands 'killing fields' trial"](http://www.time.com/time/world/article/0,8599,2053871,00.html), _BBC_ 29 December 1998], [Khmer Rouge](!Wikipedia) head of state (est. deaths: [1-2 million](!Wikipedia "Khmer Rouge#Number of deaths"))
The [sunk cost fallacy](!Wikipedia) ("Concorde fallacy", "escalation bias", "commitment effect" etc.) could be defined as when an agent ignores that option X has the highest [marginal return](!Wikipedia), and instead chooses option Y because he chose option Y many times before, or simply as "throwing good money after bad". It can be seen as an attempt to derive some gain from mistaken past choices. (A slogan for avoiding sunk costs: "give up your hopes for a better yesterday!") The single most famous example, and the reason for it also being called the "[Concorde](!Wikipedia) fallacy", would be the British and French government investing hundreds of millions of dollars into the development of a supersonic passenger jet despite knowing that it would never succeed commercially (as it did not by its last flight in 2003). Since Arkes & Blumer 1985's[^Arkes-Blumer] forceful investigation & denunciation, it has become [received wisdom](http://journals.cluteonline.com/index.php/JBER/article/download/2787/2835 "'Return the `Sunk Costs Are Sunk` Concept to Principles of Economics Textbooks', Davis 2005")[^textbooks] that sunk costs are a great bane on humanity.
But to what extent is the "sunk cost fallacy" a real fallacy?
[^textbooks]: Davis's complaint is a little odd, inasmuch as economics textbooks *do* apparently discuss sunk costs; Steele 1996 gives examples back to 1910, or from ["Do Sunk Costs Matter?"](http://www.suemialon.com/research/RevisedSunkCostsMatterApril2007.pdf), McAfee et al 2007:
> Introductory textbooks in economics present this as a basic principle and a deep truth of rational decision-making (Frank and Bernanke, 2006, p. 10, and Mankiw, 2004, p. 297).
[^Arkes-Blumer]: Arkes & Blumer 1985, [The psychology of sunk cost](http://commonsenseatheism.com/wp-content/uploads/2011/09/Arkes-Blumer-The-psychology-of-sunk-cost.pdf):
> The sunk cost effect is manifested in a greater tendency to continue an endeavor once an investment in money, effort, or time has been made. Evidence that the psychological justification for this behavior is predicated on the desire not to appear wasteful is presented. In a field study, customers who had initially paid more for a season subscription to a theater series attended more plays during the next 6 months, presumably because of their higher sunk cost in the season tickets. Several questionnaire studies corroborated and extended this finding. It is found that those who had incurred a sunk cost inflated their estimate of how likely a project was to succeed compared to the estimates of the same project by those who had not incurred a sunk cost. The basic sunk cost finding that people will throw good money after bad appears to be well described by prospect theory ([D. Kahneman & A. Tversky, 1979](http://www.princeton.edu/~kahneman/docs/Publications/prospect_theory.pdf "'Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk'"), _Econometrica_, 47, 263-291). Only moderate support for the contention that personal involvement increases the sunk cost effect is presented. The sunk cost effect was not lessened by having taken prior courses in economics. Finally, the sunk cost effect cannot be fully subsumed under any of several social psychological theories.
>
> As an example of the sunk cost effect, consider the following example [from Thaler 1980]. A man wins a contest sponsored by a local radio station. He is given a free ticket to a football game. Since he does not want to go alone, he persuades a friend to buy a ticket and go with him. As they prepare to go to the game, a terrible blizzard begins. The contest winner peers out his window over the arctic scene and announces that he is not going, because the pain of enduring the snowstorm would be greater than the enjoyment he would derive from watching the game. However, his friend protests, 'I don't want to waste the twelve dollars I paid for the ticket! I want to go!' The friend who purchased the ticket is not behaving rationally according to traditional economic theory. Only incremental costs should influence decisions, not sunk costs. If the agony of sitting in a blinding snowstorm for 3 h is greater than the enjoyment one would derive from trying to see the game, then one should not go. The $12 has been paid whether one goes or not. It is a sunk cost. It should in no way influence the decision to go. But who among us is so rational?
>
> Our final sample thus had eighteen no-discount, nineteen $2 discount, and seventeen $7 discount subjects. Since the ticket stubs were color coded, we were able to collect the stubs after each performance and determine how many persons in each group had attended each play...We performed a 3 (discount: none, $2, $7) x 2 (half of season) analysis of variance on the number of tickets used by each subject. The latter variable was a within-subjects factor. It was also the only significant source of variance, F(1,51) = 32.32, MS, = 1.81, (p < .OO). More tickets were used by each subject on the first five plays (3.57) than on the last five plays (2.09). We performed a priori tests on the number of tickets used by each of the three groups during the first half of the theater season. The no-discount group used significantly more tickets (4.11) than both the $2 discount group (3.32) and the $7 discount group (3.29), t = 1.79, 1.83, respectively, p's < .05, one tailed. The groups did not use significantly different numbers of tickets during the last half of the theater season (2.28, 1 .S4, 2.18, for the no-discount, $2 discount, and $7 discount groups, respectively). *Conclusion*. Those who had purchased theater tickets at the normal price used more theater tickets during the first half of the season than those who purchased tickets at either of the two discounts. According to rational economic theory, after all subjects had their ticket booklet in hand, they should have been equally likely to attend the plays.
>
> ...A second feature of prospect theory pertinent to sunk costs is the certainty effect. This effect is manifested in two ways. First, absolutely *certain* gains (p = 1) are greatly overvalued. By this we mean that the value of certain gains is higher than what would be expected given an analysis of a person's values of gains having a probability less than 1.0. Second, certain losses (p = 1.0) are greatly undervalued (i.e., further from zero). The value is more negative than what would be expected given an analysis of a person's values of losses having a probability less than 1.0. In other words, certainty magnifies both positive and negative values. Note that in question 3A the decision not to complete the plane results in a certain loss of the amount already invested. Since prospect theory states that certain losses are particularly aversive, we might predict that subjects would find the other option comparatively attractive. This is in fact what occurred. Whenever a sunk cost dilemma involves the choice of a certain loss (stop the waterway project) versus a long shot (maybe it will become profitable by the year 2500), the certainty effect favors the latter option.
>
> ...Fifty-nine students had taken at least one course; sixty-one had taken no such course. All of these students were administered the Experiment 1 questionnaire by a graduate student in psychology. A third group comprised 61 students currently enrolled in an economics course, who were administered the Experiment 1 questionnaire by their economics professor during an economics class. Approximately three fourths of the students in this group had also taken one prior economics course. All of the economics students had been exposed to the concept of sunk cost earlier that semester both in their textbook (Gwartney & Stroup, 1982, p. 125 [_Microeconomics: Private and public choice_]) and in their class lectures. Results. Table 1 contains the results. The x^2^ analysis does not approach significance. Even when an economics teacher in an economics class hands out a sunk cost questionnaire to economics students, there is no more conformity to rational economic theory than in the other two groups. We conclude that general instruction in economics does not lessen the sunk cost effect. In a recent analysis of entrapment experiments, [Northcraft and Wolf (1984)](/docs/sunkcosts/1984-northcraft.pdf) concluded that continued investment in many of them does not necessarily represent an economically irrational behavior. For example, continued waiting for the bus will increase the probability that one's waiting behavior will be rewarded. Therefore there is an eminently rational basis for continued patience. Hence this situation is not a pure demonstration of the sunk cost effect. However, we believe that *some* sunk cost situations do correspond to entrapment situations. The subjects who 'owned' the airline company would have endured continuing expenditures on the plane as they sought the eventual goal of financial rescue. This corresponds to the Brockner et al. entrapment situation. However, entrapment is irrelevant to the analysis of all our other studies. For example, people who paid more money last September for the season theater tickets are in no way trapped. They do not incur small continuous losses as they seek an eventual goal. Therefore we suggest that entrapment is relevant only to the subset of sunk cost situations in which continuing losses are endured in the hope of later rescue by a further investment.
>
> According to Thomas 1981 [_Microeconomic applications: Understanding the American economy_], one person who recognized it as an error was none other than [Thomas A. Edison](!Wikipedia). In the 1880s Edison was not making much money on his great invention, the electric lamp. The problem was that his manufacturing plant was not operating at full capacity because he could not sell enough of his lamps. He then got the idea to boost his plant's production to full capacity and sell each extra lamp below its total cost of production. His associates thought this was an exceedingly poor idea, but Edison did it anyway. By increasing his plant's output, Edison would add only 2% to the cost of production while increasing production 25%. Edison was able to do this because so much of the manufacturing cost was sunk cost. It would be present whether or not he manufactured more bulbs. [the Europe price > marginal cost] Edison then sold the large number of extra lamps in Europe for much more than the small *added* manufacturing costs. Since production increases involved negligible new costs but substantial new income, Edison was wise to increase production. While Edison was able to place sunk costs in proper perspective in arriving at his decision, our research suggests that most of the rest of us find that very difficult to do.
Friedman et al 2006 criticism of Arkes:
> This is consistent with the sunk cost fallacy, but the evidence is not as strong as one might hope. The reported significance levels apparently assume that (apart from the excluded couples) all attendance choices are independent. The authors do not explain why they divided the season in half, nor do they report the significance levels for the entire season (or first quarter, etc.). The data show no significant difference between the small and large discount groups in the first half season nor among any of the groups in the second half season. We are not aware of any replication of this field experiment.
Below, I argue the following:
1. sunk costs are probably issues in big organizations
- but maybe not ones that can be helped
2. sunk costs are not issues in animals
3. sunk costs appear to exist in children & adults
- but many apparent instances of the fallacy are better explained as part of a learning strategy
- and there's little evidence sunk cost-like behavior leads to *actual* problems in individuals
5. much of what we call "sunk cost" looks like simple carelessness & thoughtlessness
# Subtleties
> One cannot proceed from the informal to the formal by formal means.^[--[Alan Perlis](!Wikipedia), "[Epigrams on Programming](!Wikipedia)"]
*A* "sunk cost fallacy" obviously is a fallacy in a simple model: 'imagine an agent _A_ who chooses between option _X_ which will return $10 and option _Y_ which will return \$6, and agent _A_ in previous rounds chose _Y_'. Obviously if _A_ chooses _X_, it will be better off by $4 than if it chooses _Y_. This is correct and as hard to dispute as '_A_ implies _B_; _A_; therefore _B_'. We can call both examples *[valid](!Wikipedia "Validity")*. But in philosophy, when we discuss [modus ponens](Prediction markets#modus-tollens-vs-modus-ponens), we agree that it is always valid, but we do not always agree that it is *[sound](!Wikipedia "Soundness")*: that A does in fact imply B, or that A really is the case, and so B is the case. 'The moon being made of cheese implies the astronauts walked on cheese; the moon is made of cheese; therefore the astronauts walked on cheese' is logically valid, but not sound, since we don't think that the moon is made of cheese. Or we differ with the first line as well, pointing out that only some of the Apollo astronauts walked on the moon. We reject the soundness.
We can and must do the same thing in economics - but _ceteris_ is never _paribus_. In simple models, sunk cost is clearly a valid fallacy to be avoided. But is the real world compliant enough to make the fallacy sound? Notice the assumptions we had to make: we wish away issues of risk (and risk aversion), long-delayed consequences, changes in options as a result of past investment, and so on.
We can illustrate this by looking at an even more sacred aspect of normative economics: [exponential discounting](!Wikipedia). One of the key justifications of exponential discounting is that any other discounting can be money-pumped by an exponential agent investing at each time period at whatever the prevailing return is or loaning at appropriate times. ([George Ainslie](!Wikipedia "George Ainslie (psychologist)") in [_The Breakdown of Will_](http://www.amazon.com/Breakdown-Will-George-Ainslie/dp/0521596947/) gives the example of a hyperbolic agent improvidently selling its winter coat every spring and buying it just before the snowstorms every winter, being money-pumped by the consistent exponential agent.) One of the assumptions is that certain rates of investment return will be available; but in the real world, rates can stagger around for long periods. ["Hyperbolic discounting is rational: valuing the far future with uncertain discount rates"](http://cowles.econ.yale.edu/P/cd/d17a/d1719.pdf) (Farmer & Geanakoplos 2009)[^popularization] argues that if returns follow a more geometric random walk, hyperbolic discounting is superior[^farmer]. Are they correct? They are not [much-cited](http://scholar.google.com/scholar?cites=15313265516116473249 "Google Scholar-listed citations of Farmer & Geanakoplos 2009") or criticized. But even if they are wrong about hyperbolic discounting, it needs proving that exponential discounting *does* in fact deal correctly with changing returns. (The market over the past few years has not turned in the proverbial 8-9% annual returns, and one wonders if there will ever be a big bull market that makes up for the great stagnation.)
[^popularization]: Popularized discussions of Farmer & Geanakoplos 2009:
- ["'Discounting' the future cost of climate change"](http://www.sciencenews.org/view/generic/id/59509/title/Math_Trek__Discounting_the_future_cost_of_climate_change), _Science News_
- ["Einstein on Wall Street, Time-Money Continuum: Mark Buchanan"](http://www.bloomberg.com/news/2011-07-28/einstein-on-wall-street-time-money-continuum-commentary-by-mark-buchanan.html), _WSJ_ column
- ["Discounting Details"](http://physicsoffinance.blogspot.com/2011/07/discountingdetails.html), on Mark Buchanan's blog ["The Physics of Finance"](http://physicsoffinance.blogspot.com/)
[^farmer]: Some quotes from the paper:
> Conventional economics supposes that agents value the present vs. the future using an exponential discounting function. In contrast, experiments with animals and humans suggest that agents are better described as hyperbolic discounters, whose discount function decays much more slowly at large times, as a power law. This is generally regarded as being time inconsistent or irrational. We show that when agents cannot be sure of their own future one-period discount rates, then hyperbolic discounting can become rational and exponential discounting irrational. This has important implications for environmental economics, as it implies a much larger weight for the far future.
>
> ...Why should we discount the future? Bohm-Bawerk (1889,1923) and Fisher (1930) argued that men were naturally impatient, perhaps owing to a failure of the imagination in conjuring the future as vividly as the present. Another justification for declining Ds (τ ) in τ, given by Rae (1834,1905), is that people are mortal, so survival probabilities must enter the calculation of the benefits of future potential consumption. There are many possible reasons for discounting, as reviewed by Dasgupta (2004, 2008). Most economic analysis assumes exponential discounting Ds (τ ) = D(τ ) = exp(−rτ ), as originally posited by Samuelson (1937) and put on an axiomatic foundation by Koopmans (1960). A natural justification for exponential discounting comes from financial economics and the opportunity cost of foregoing an investment. A dollar at time s can be placed in the bank to collect interest at rate r, and if the interest rate is constant, it will generate exp(r(t − s)) dollars at time t. A dollar at time t is therefore equivalent to exp(−r(t − s)) dollars at time s. Letting τ = t − s, this motivates the exponential discount function Ds (τ ) = D(τ ) = exp(−rτ ), independent of s.
>
> ...For roughly the first eighty years the certainty equivalent discount function for the geometric random walk stays fairly close to the exponential, but afterward the two diverge substantially, with the geometric random walk giving a much larger weight to the future. A comparison using more realistic parameters is given in Table 1. For large times the difference is dramatic.
>
> year GRW exponential
> ---- --- -----------
> 20 0.462 0.456
> 60 0.125 0.095
> 100 0.051 0.020
> 500 0.008 2 × 10^−9^
> 1000 0.005 4 × 10^−18^
>
> ...What this analysis makes clear, however, is that the long term behavior of valuations depends extremely sensitively on the interest rate model. The fact that the present value of actions that affect the far future can shift from a few percentage points to infinity when we move from a constant interest rate to a geometric random walk calls seriously into question many well regarded analyses of the economic consequences of global warming. ... no fixed discount rate is really adequate - as our analysis makes abundantly clear, the proper discounting function is not an exponential.
If we look at sunk cost literature, we must keep many things in mind. For example:
1. organization versus individuals
Sunk costs seem especially common in groups, as has been noticed since the beginning of sunk cost research[^Staw-1981-groups]; [Khan et al 2000](/docs/sunkcosts/2000-khan.pdf "Throwing Good Money After Bad: A Comparison of Asian and Developed Country Managerial Decision-Making in Sunk Cost Situations") found that culture influenced how much managers were willing to engage in hypothetical sunk costs (South & East Asian more so than North American), and a 2005 meta-analysis that sunk cost was an issue, especially in software-related projects[^software], agreeing with a 2009 meta-analysis, [Desai & Chulkov](http://cluteonline.com/journals/index.php/IJMIS/article/download/4944/5036 "Escalation Of Commitment In MIS Projects: A Meta-Analysis"). [Mukerjee 2011](/docs/sunkcosts/2011-mukerjee.pdf "Why Do Educational Administrators and Other Stakeholders Fail to Recognize and Learn From Failure? What Lessons Can We Learn From Theories of Irrational Behavior?") interviewed principals at Californian schools, finding evidence of sunk cost bias. Wikipedia characterizes the Concorde incident as "regarded privately by the British government as a 'commercial disaster' which should never have been started, and was almost canceled, but political and legal issues had ultimately made it impossible for either government to pull out." So at every point, coalitions of politicians and bureaucrats found it in their self-interest to keep the ball rolling. A sunk cost for the government or nation as a whole is far from the same thing as a sunk cost for those coalitions - responsibility is diffused, which encourages sunk cost[^diffusion] (If Kennedy or other US presidents could not withdraw from Vietnam or [Iraq](http://www.slate.com/articles/news_and_politics/hey_wait_a_minute/2005/09/the_sunkcost_fallacy.html "The Sunk-Cost Fallacy: Bush falls victim to a bad new argument for the Iraq war")[^Iraq] or Afghanistan[^Afghanistan] due to perceived sunk costs[^Dawkins], perhaps the real problem was why Americans thought Vietnam was so important and why they feared looking weak or provoking another ["who lost China"](!Wikipedia "China_Hands#The men who .22lost.22 China") debate.) People commit sunk cost much more easily if someone else is paying, possibly in part because they are trying to still prove themselves right - an understandable and rational choice[^fiddler]! Other anecdotes from [Bazerman & Neale 1992](/docs/sunkcosts/1992-bazerman.pdf "Nonrational escalation of commitment in negotiation") suggest sunk cost can be expensive corporate problems, but of course are only anecdotes; [Robert Campeau](!Wikipedia "Robert Campeau#Corporate take-overs and bankruptcy") killed his company by escalating to an impossibly expensive acquisition of [Bloomingdale's](!Wikipedia) but would Campeau ever have been a good corporate raider without his aggressiveness; or can we say the Philip Morris-Proctor & Gamble [coffee price war](http://money.cnn.com/magazines/fortune/fortune_archive/1990/05/21/73551/index.htm "CAN ANYONE WIN THE COFFEE WAR? The lesson from the endless, almost comic, battle between Philip Morris's Maxwell House and P&G's Folgers: Market share isn't always what it's cracked up to be") was a mistake without a great deal more information; and was Bobby Fischer's vendetta against the Soviet Union sunk cost or a rational strategy to Soviet collusion or simply an early symptom of the apparent mental issues that saw him converting to and impoverished by a peculiar church and ultimately an internally persecuted convict in Iceland?
And why were those coalitions in power in the first place? France and Britain have not found any better systems of government - systems which operate efficiently and are also Nash equilibriums, which successfully avoid any sunk costs in their myriads of projects and initiatives. In [Joseph Tainter](!Wikipedia)'s 1988 [_Collapse of Complex Societies_](http://www.amazon.com/Collapse-Complex-Societies-Studies-Archaeology/dp/052138673X/), he argues that societies that overreach do so because it is impossible for the organizations and members to back down on complexity as long as there is still wealth to extract, even when [margins are diminishing](!Wikipedia "Diminishing returns"); when we accuse [Pueblo Indians](http://www.santafe.edu/media/workingpapers/02-02-007.pdf) [of sunk cost](http://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol9/iss1/art6/main.html) and causing their civilization to collapse[^Pueblo], we should keep in mind there may be no governance alternatives. Debacles like the Concorde may be necessary because the alternatives are even worse - decision paralysis or institutional paranoia[^paranoia]. Aggressive policing of projects for sunk-costs may wind up [violating Chesterton's fence](http://unenumerated.blogspot.com/2012/08/proxy-measures-sunk-costs-and.html) if managers in later time periods are not very clear on why the projects were started in the first place and what their benefits will be. If we successfully 'avoid' sunk cost-style reasoning, does that mean we will avoid future Vietnams, at the expense of World War IIs?[^McAfee-war] [Goodhart's Law](!Wikipedia) comes to mind here, particularly because one study recorded how a bank's attempt to eliminate sunk cost bias in its loan officers resulted in backfiring and evasion[^banks]; the overall results seem to still have been an improvement, but it remains a cautionary lesson.
Whatever pressures and feedback loops cause sunk cost fallacy in organizations may be *completely* different from the causes in individuals.
2. Non-monetary rewards and penalties
["Individual organisms are best thought of as adaptation-executers rather than as fitness-maximizers."](http://lesswrong.com/lw/l0/adaptationexecuters_not_fitnessmaximizers/) What does this mean in a sunk cost context? That we should be aware that humans may not treat the model at its literal face value (without careful thought or strong encouragement to do so, anyway), treat the situation as simply as '$10 versus $6 (and sunk cost)'. It may be more like '$10 (and your - non-existent - tribe's condemnation of you as greedy, insincere, small-minded, and disloyal) versus $6 (and sunk cost)'[^Pinker]. If humans really are forced to think like this, then the modeling of payoffs simply doesn't correspond with reality and of course our judgements will be wrong. Some assumptions spit out sunk costs as rational strategies[^McAfee-reputation]. This is not a trivial issue here (see the self-justification literature, eg. Brockner 1981) or in other areas; for example, providing the correct amount of rewards caused many differences in levels of animal intelligence to simply vanish - the rewards had been unequal (see my excerpts of the essay ["If a Lion Could Talk: Animal Intelligence and the Evolution of Consciousness"](Drug heuristics#fn46)).
3. Sunk costs versus investments
Many choices for lower immediate marginal return are investments for greater future return. A single-stage model cannot capture this.
4. Demonstrated harm
It's not enough to suggest that a behavior may be harmful; it needs to be demonstrated. One might argue that an all-you-can-eat buffet will cause overeating and then long-term harm to health, but [do experiments bear out](/docs/sunkcosts/2012-siniver.pdf "'All-You-Can-Eat Buffet: Entry Price, the Fat Tax and Meal Cessation', Siniver & Yaniv 2012") that theory?
[^diffusion]: ["Diffusion of Responsibility: Effects on the Escalation Tendency"](http://www.csub.edu/~mdulcich/documents/diffusion_of_responsibility.pdf), Whyte 1991 (see also [Whyte 1993](/docs/sunkcosts/1993-whyte.pdf "Escalating commitment in individual and group decision-making: a prospect theory approach")):
> In a laboratory study, the possibility was investigated that group decision making in the initial stages of an investment project might reduce the escalation tendency by diffusing responsibility for initiating a failing project. Support for this notion was found. Escalation effects occurred less frequently and were less severe among individuals described as participants in a group decision to initiate a failing course of action than among individuals described as personally responsible for the initial decision. Self-justification theory was found to be less relevant after group than after individual decisions. Because most decisions about important new policies in organizations are made by groups, these results indicate a gap in theorizing about the determinants of escalating commitment for an important category of escalation situations.
>
> ...The impact of personal responsibility on persistence in error has been replicated several times (e.g., Bazerman, Beekun, & Schoorman, 1982; Caldwell & O'Reilly, 1982; Staw, 1976; Staw & Fox, 1977).
[^Staw-1981-groups]: For example, Staw 1981, ["The Escalation of Commitment to a Course of Action"](/docs/sunkcosts/1981-staw.pdf):
> A second way to explain decisional errors is to attribute a breakdown in rationality to interpersonal elements such as social power or group dynamics. Pfeffer [1977] has, for example, outlined how and when power considerations are likely to outweigh more rational aspects of organizational decision making, and Janis [1972] has noted many problems in the decision making of policy groups. Cohesive groups may, according to Janis, suppress dissent, censor information, create illusions of invulnerability, and stereotype enemies. Any of these by-products of social interaction may, of course, hinder rational decision making and lead individuals or groups to decisional errors.
[^paranoia]: Janssen & Scheffer 2004:
> In fact, escalation of commitment is found in group decision making ([Bazerman et al. 1984](/docs/sunkcosts/1984-bazerman.pdf)). Members of a group strive for unanimity. A typical goal for political decisions within small-scale societies is to reach consensus ([Boehm 1996](/docs/sunkcosts/1996-boehm.pdf)). Once unanimity is reached, the easiest way to protect it is to stay committed to the group's decision (Bazerman et al. 1984, Janis 1972 [_Victims of groupthink_]). Thus, when the group is faced with a negative feedback, members will not suggest abandoning the earlier course of action, because this might disrupt the existing unanimity.
[^fiddler]: The former can be found in [Bazerman, Giuliano, & Appelman, 1984](/docs/sunkcosts/1984-bazerman.pdf), [Davis & Bobko, 1986](/docs/sunkcosts/1986-davis.pdf), & [Staw, 1976](http://classwebs.spea.indiana.edu/kenricha/Oxford/Archives/Courses%202010/Decision%20Making%202010/Articles/staw1976%20-%20Knee%20Deep.pdf) among other studies cited here. The latter is often called 'self-justification' or the 'justification effect' (eg. [Brockner 1992](/docs/sunkcosts/1992-brockner.pdf)).
Self-justification is, of course, in many contexts a valuable trait to have; is the following an error, or business students demonstrating their precocious understanding of an invaluable bureaucratic in-fighting skill? Bazerman et al 1982, ["Performance evaluation in a dynamic context: A laboratory study of the impact of prior commitment to the ratee"](/docs/sunkcosts/1982-bazerman.pdf) (see also Caldwell & O'Reilly, 1982; Staw, 1976; Staw & Fox, 1977):
> A dynamic view of performance evaluation is proposed that argues that raters who are provided with negative performance data on a previously promoted employee will subsequently evaluate the employee more positively if they, rather than their predecessors, made the earlier promotion decision. A total of 298 business majors participated in the study. The experimental group made a promotion decision by choosing among three candidates, whereas the control group was told that the decision had been made by someone else. Both groups evaluated the promoted employee's performance after reviewing 2 years of data. The hypothesized escalation of commitment effect was observed in that the experimental group consistently evaluated the employee more favorably, provided larger rewards, and made more optimistic projections of future performance than did the control group.
[^Dawkins]: Dawkins & Carlisle 1976 sarcastically remark:
> ...The idea has been influential^4^, and it appeals to economic intuition. A government which has invested heavily in, for example, a supersonic airliner, is understandably reluctant to abandon it, even when sober judgement of future prospects suggests that it should do so. Similarly, a popular argument against American withdrawal from the Vietnam war was a retrospective one: 'We cannot allow those boys to have died in vain'. Intuition says that previous investment commits one to future investment.
[^Pueblo]: And it is difficult to judge from a distance when sunk cost has occurred: what exactly else are the Indians going to invest in? Remember our exponential discounting example. As long as various settlements are not running at an outright loss or are being subsidized, how steep an opportunity cost do they really face? From the paper:
> By the end of the occupation in the late-A.D. 800s there is evidence of depletion of wood resources, pi on seeds, and animals (reviewed by Kohler 1992). Following the collapse of these villages, the Dolores area was never reoccupied in force by Puebloan farmers. A second similar case comes from nearby Sand Canyon Locality west of Cortez, Colorado, intensively studied by the Crow Canyon Archaeological Center over the last 15 years (Lipe 1992). Here the main occupation is several hundred years later than in Dolores, but the patterns of construction in hamlets versus villages are similar (fig. 4, bottom). The demise of the two villages contributing dated construction events to fig. 4 (bottom) coincides with the famous depopulation of the Four Corners region of the U.S. Southwest. There is strong evidence for declining availability of protein in general and large game animals in particular, and increased competition for the best agricultural land, during the terminal occupation (reviewed by Kohler 2000). We draw a final example from an intermediate period. The most famous Anasazi structures, the "great houses" of Chaco Canyon, may follow a similar pattern. Windes and Ford (1996) show that early construction episodes (in the early A.D. 900s) in the canyon great houses typically coincide with periods of high potential agricultural productivity, but later construction continues in both good periods and bad, particularly in the poor period from ca. A.D. 1030-1050.
Certainly there is strong evidence of diminishing marginal returns - evidence for the Tainter thesis - but *diminishing marginal returns is not sunk cost fallacy*. Given the general environment, and given that there was a 'collapse', arguably there was *no* opportunity cost to remaining there. How would the Indians have become better off if they abandoned their villages, given that there is little evidence that other places were better off in that period of great droughts and the obvious observation that they would need to make substantial capital investments in wherever they went?
[^banks]: ["Banking on Commitment: Intended and Unintended Consequences of an Organization's Attempt to Attenuate Escalation of Commitment"](/docs/sunkcosts/2002-mcnamara.pdf), McNamara et al 2002:
> The notion that decision makers tend to incorrectly consider previous expenditures when deliberating current utility-based decisions (Arkes & Blumer, 1985) has been used to explain fiascoes ranging from the prolonged involvement of the United States in the Vietnam War to the disastrous cost overrun during the construction of the [Shoreham Nuclear Power Plant](!Wikipedia) (Ross & Staw, 1993). In the Shoreham Nuclear Power Plant example, escalation of commitment meant billions of wasted dollars (Ross & Staw, 1993). In the Vietnam War, it may have cost thousands of lives...Kirby and Davis's (1998) experimental study showed that increased monitoring could dampen the escalation of commitment. Staw, Barsade, and Koput's (1997) field data on the banking industry led them to conclude that top manager turnover led to de-escalation of commitment at an aggregate level.
>
> ...So far, the results support the efficacy of changes in monitoring and decision responsibility as cures for the escalation of commitment bias. We now turn to the side effects of these treatments. Hypotheses 4 and 5 propose that the threat of increased monitoring and change in management responsibility increase the likelihood of a different form of undesirable decision commitment - the persistent underassessment of borrower risk. The results in column 3 of Table 2 support these hypotheses. Both the threat of increased monitoring and the threat of change in decision responsibility increase the likelihood of persistent underassessment of borrower risk (.47, _p_<.01, and .50, _p_<.05, respectively). These findings support the view that decision makers are likely to fail to appropriately downgrade a borrower when, by doing so, they avoid an organizational intervention. We examined the change in investment commitment for borrowers whose risk was persistently underassessed and who faced either increased monitoring or change in decision responsibility if the decision makers had admitted that the risk needed downgrading. We found that decision makers did appear to exhibit escalation of commitment to these borrowers. The change in commitment (on average, over 30%) is significantly greater than 0 (t = 2.94, _p_<.01) and greater than the change in commitment to those borrowers who were correctly assessed as remaining at the same risk level (t = 2.58, _p_=.01). Combined, these findings suggest that although the organizational efforts to minimize undesirable decision commitment appeared successful at first glance, the threat of these interventions increased the likelihood that decision makers would persistently give overfavorable assessments of the risk of borrowers. In turn, the lending officers would then escalate their monetary commitment to these riskier borrowers.
On nuclear power plants as sunk cost fallacy, McAfee et al 2007:
> According to evidence reported by [De Bondt and Makhija (1988)](http://behavioralfinance.depaul.edu/docs/PublicationsResources/232.pdf "Throwing Good Money After Bad? Nuclear Power Plant Investment Decisions and the Relevance of Sunk Costs"), managers of many utility companies in the U.S. have been overly reluctant to terminate economically unviable nuclear plant projects. In the 1960s, the nuclear power industry promised "energy too cheap to meter." But nuclear power later proved unsafe and uneconomical. As the U.S. nuclear power program was failing in the 1970s and 1980s, Public Service Commissions around the nation ordered prudency reviews. From these reviews, De Bondt and Makhija find evidence that the Commissions denied many utility companies even partial recovery of nuclear construction costs on the grounds that they had been mismanaging the nuclear construction projects in ways consistent with "throwing good money after bad."...In most projects there is uncertainty, and restarting after stopping entails costs, making the option to continue valuable. This is certainly the case for nuclear power plants, for example. Shutting down a nuclear reactor requires dismantling or entombment, and the costs of restarting are extremely high. Moreover, the variance of energy prices has been quite large. The option of maintaining nuclear plants is therefore potentially valuable. Low returns from nuclear power in the 1970s and 1980s might have been a consequence of the large variance, suggesting a high option value of maintaining nuclear plants. This may in part explain the evidence (reported by De Bondt and Makhija, 1988) that managers of utilities at the time were so reluctant to shut down seemingly unprofitable plants.
[^Pinker]: [Steven Pinker](!Wikipedia), _[The Better Angels of Our Nature](!Wikipedia)_ 2011, pg 336:
> In the case of a war of attrition, one can imagine a leader who has a changing willingness to suffer a cost over time, increasing as the conflict proceeds and his resolve toughens. His motto would be: 'We fight on so that our boys shall not have died in vain.' This mindset, known as loss aversion, the sunk-cost fallacy, and throwing good money after bad, is patently irrational, but it is surprisingly pervasive in human decision-making.^65^ People stay in an abusive marriage because of the years they have already put into it, or sit through a bad movie because they have already paid for the ticket, or try to reverse a gambling loss by doubling their next bet, or pour money into a boondoggle because they've already poured so much money into it. Though psychologists don't fully understand why people are suckers for sunk costs, a common explanation is that it signals a public commitment. The person is announcing: 'When I make a decision, I'm not so weak, stupid, or indecisive that I can be easily talked out of it.' In a contest of resolve like an attrition game, loss aversion could serve as a costly and hence credible signal that the contestant is not about to concede, preempting his opponent's strategy of outlasting him just one more round.
It's worth noting that there is at least one example of sunk cost ("entry licenses" [fees]) encouraging cooperation ("collusive price path") in market agents: Offerman & Potter 2001, ["Does Auctioning of Entry Licenses Induce Collusion? An Experimental Study"](http://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/download?doi=10.1.1.200.683&rep=rep1&type=pdf), who point out another case of how our sunk cost map may not correspond to the territory:
> There is one caveat to the sunk cost argument, however. If the game for which the positions are allocated has multiple equilibria, an entry fee may affect the equilibrium that is being selected. Several experimental studies have demonstrated the force of this principle. For example, [Cooper, DeJong, Forsythe and Ross (1993)](/docs/sunkcosts/1993-cooper.pdf "Forward Induction in the Battle-of-the-Sexes Games"), [Van Huyck, Battalio and Beil (1993)](/docs/sunkcosts/1993-huyck.pdf "Asset Markets as an Equilibrium Selection Mechanism: Coordination Failure, Game Form Auctions and Tacit Communication"), and [Cachon and Camerer, (1996)](/docs/sunkcosts/1996-cachon.pdf "Loss avoidance and Forward Induction in Experimental Coordination Games") study coordination games with multiple equilibria and find that an entry fee may induce players to coordinate on a different (Pareto superior) equilibrium.
[^McAfee-reputation]: McAfee et al 2007
> *Reputational Concerns*. In team relationships, each participant's willingness to invest depends on the investments of others. In such circumstances, a commitment to finishing projects even when they appear _ex post_ unprofitable is valuable, because such a commitment induces more efficient _ex ante_ investment. Thus, a reputation for "throwing good money after bad" - the classic sunk cost fallacy - can solve a coordination problem. In contrast to the desire for commitment, people might rationally want to conceal bad choices to appear more talented, which may lead them to make further investments, hoping to conceal their investments gone bad.
>
> [Kanodia, Bushman, and Dickhaut (1989)](/docs/sunkcosts/1989-kanodia.pdf "Escalation Errors and the Sunk Cost Effect: An Explanation Based on Reputation and Information Asymmetries"), [Prendergast and Stole (1996)](http://faculty.chicagobooth.edu/canice.prendergast/research/impetuousYoungstersAndJadedOldTimes.pdf "Impetuous Youngsters and Jaded Old-Timers: Acquiring a Reputation for Learning"), and Camerer and Weber (1999) develop principal-agent models in which rational agents invest more if they have invested more in the past to protect their reputation for ability. We elucidate the general features of these models below and argue that concerns about reputation for ability are especially powerful in explaining apparent reactions to sunk costs by politicians. [Carmichael and MacLeod (2003)](http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=200776 "Caring About Sunk Costs: A Behavioral Solution to Holdup Problems With Small Stakes") [see also [Carpenter & Matthews 2003](http://sandcat.middlebury.edu/econ/repec/mdl/ancoec/0312.pdf "Crying Over Spilt Milk: Sunk Costs, Fairness Norms, and the Hold-Up Problem")] develop a model in which agents initially make investments independently and are later matched in pairs, their match produces a surplus, and they bargain over it based on cultural norms of fair division. A fair division rule in which each agent's surplus share is increasing in their sunk investment, and decreasing in the other's sunk investment, is shown to be evolutionarily stable.
>
> ...If a member of an illegal price-fixing cartel seems likely to confess to the government in exchange for immunity from prosecution, the other cartel members may race to be first to confess, since only the first gets immunity (in Europe, such immunity is called "leniency"). Similarly, a spouse who loses faith in the long-term prospects of a marriage invests less in the relationship, thereby reducing the gains from partnership, potentially dooming the relationship. In both cases, beliefs about the future viability matter to the success of the relationship, and there is the potential for self-fulfilling optimistic and pessimistic beliefs.
>
> In such a situation, individuals may rationally select others who stay in the relationship beyond the point of individual rationality, if such a commitment is possible. Indeed, _ex ante_ it is rational to construct exit barriers like costly and difficult divorce laws, so as to reduce early exit. Such exit barriers might be behavioral as well as legal. If an individual can develop a reputation for sticking in a relationship beyond the break-even point, it would make that individual a more desirable partner and thus enhance the set of available partners, as well as encourage greater and longer lasting investment by the chosen partner. One way of creating such a reputation is to act as if one cares about sunk costs...We now formalize this concept using a simple two-period model that sets aside consideration of selection....That is, a slight possibility of breach is collectively harmful; both agents would be _ex ante_ better off if they could prevent breach when _V − ρ < 1_, which holds as long as the reputation cost _ρ_ of breaching is not too small. In this model, a tendency to stay in the relationship due to a large sunk investment would be beneficial to each party.
[^McAfee-war]: McAfee et al 2007:
> But there are also examples of people who succeeded by not ignoring sunk costs. The same "we-owe-it-to-our-fallen-countrymen" logic that led Americans to stay the course in Vietnam also helped the war effort in World War II. More generally, many success stories involve people who at some time suffered great setbacks, but persevered when short-term odds were not in their favor because they "had already come too far to give up now." Columbus did not give up when the shores of India did not appear after weeks at sea, and many on his crew were urging him to turn home (see Olson, 1967 [_The Northmen, Columbus and Cabot, 985-1503_], for Columbus' journal). Jeff Bezos, founder of Amazon.com, did not give up when Amazon's loss totaled $1.4 billion in 2001, and many on Wall Street were speculating that the company would go broke (see [Mendelson and Meza, 2001](http://gsbapps.stanford.edu/cases/documents/EC25.pdf "Amazon.com: Marching Toward Profitability")).
[^Afghanistan]: Kelly 2004:
> The physicist [Eugene Demler](http://cmt.harvard.edu/demler/) informs me that exactly parallel arguments were quite commonly made in the Soviet Union in the late 1980s in an attempt to justify continued Soviet involvement in Afghanistan.
[^software]: [Wang & Keil 2005](http://www.irma-international.org/viewtitle/32583/ "A Meta-Analysis of the Sunk Cost Effect on Project Escalation"); from the abstract:
> Using meta-analysis, we analyzed the results of 20 sunk cost experiments and found: (1) a large effect size associated with sunk costs, (2) variability of effect sizes across experiments that was larger than pure subject-level sampling error, and (3) stronger effects in experiments involving IT projects as opposed to non-IT projects.
Background on why one might expect effects with *IT* in particular:
> Although project escalation is a general phenomenon, IT project escalation has received considerable attention since Keil and his colleagues began studying the phenomenon (Keil, Mixon et al. 1995). Survey data suggest that 30-40% of all IT projects involve some degree of project escalation (Keil, Mann, and Rai 2000). To study the role of sunk cost in software project escalation, Keil et al. (1995) conducted a series of lab experiments, in which sunk costs were manipulated at various levels, and subjects decided whether or not to continue an IT project facing negative prospects. This IT version of the sunk cost experiment was later replicated across cultures (Keil, Tan et al. 2000), with group decision makers (Boonthanom 2003), and under different de-escalation situations (Heng, Tan et al. 2003). These experiments demonstrated the sunk cost effect to be significant in IT project escalation.
The "real option" defense of sunk cost behavior has been suggested for software projects ([Tiwana & Fichman (2006)](http://tiwana.myweb.uga.edu/pdfs/j/ds06.pdf "Information systems project continuation in escalation situations: A real options model"))
[^Iraq]: Both of them - but the [first one](!Wikipedia "Gulf War") on the Iraqi side, specifically [Saddam Hussein](!Wikipedia); Bazerman & Neale 1992:
> Similarly, it could be argued that in the Iraqi/Kuwait conflict, Iraq (Hussein) had the information necessary to rationally pursue a negotiated settlement. In fact, early on in the crisis, he was offered a package for settlement that was far better than anything that he could have expected through a continued conflict. The escalation literature accurately predicts that the initial "investment" incurred in invading Kuwait would lead Iraq to a further escalation of its commitment not to compromise on the return of Kuwait.
# Animals
>> It really is the hardest thing in life for people to decide when to cut their losses.
>
> No, it's not. All you have to do is to periodically pretend that you were magically teleported into your current situation. Anything else is the sunk cost fallacy.^[--"John", [_Overcoming Bias_](http://lesswrong.com/lw/i9/the_importance_of_saying_oops/ejg)]
Point 3 leads us to an interesting point about sunk cost: it has only been identified in humans, or primates at the widest^[The qualifier is because hyperbolic discounting has been demonstrated in many primates, and a number of other biases, eg Chen et al 2006, ["How Basic Are Behavioral Biases? Evidence from Capuchin Monkey Trading Behavior"](http://www.yale.edu/monkeylab/Main/Research_files/chenetal.2006.pdf)].
Arkes & Ayton 1999 (["The Sunk Cost and Concorde Effects: Are Humans Less Rational Than Lower Animals?"](http://americandreamcoalition-org.adcblog.org/transit/sunkcosteffect.pdf)) claims (see also the very similar [Curio 1987](/docs/sunkcosts/1987-curio.pdf)):
> The sunk cost effect is a maladaptive economic behavior that is manifested in a greater tendency to continue an endeavor once an investment in money, effort, or time has been made. The Concorde fallacy is another name for the sunk cost effect, except that the former term has been applied strictly to lower animals, whereas the latter has been applied solely to humans. The authors contend that there are no unambiguous instances of the Concorde fallacy in lower animals and also present evidence that young children, when placed in an economic situation akin to a sunk cost one, exhibit more normatively correct behavior than do adults. These findings pose an enigma: Why do adult humans commit an error contrary to the normative cost-benefit rules of choice, whereas children and phylogenetically humble organisms do not? The authors attempt to show that this paradoxical state of affairs is due to humans' overgeneralization of the "Don't waste" rule.
Specifically, in [1972 Trivers](http://web.archive.org/web/20110401034305/www.anthro.utah.edu/PDFs/trivers1972.pdf "Parental Investment and Sexual Selection") proposed that fathers are more likely to abandon children, and mothers less likely, because fathers invest less resources into children - mothers are, in effect, committing sunk cost fallacy in taking care of them. [Dawkins & Carlisle 1976](/docs/sunkcosts/1976-dawkins.pdf "Parental investment, mate desertion and a fallacy") pointed out that this is a misapplication of sunk cost, a version of point #3; Arkes & Ayton's summary:
> If parental resources become depleted, to which of the two offspring should nurturance be given? According to Trivers's analysis, the older of the two offspring has received more parental investment by dint of its greater age, so the parent or parents will favor it. This would be an example of a past investment governing a current choice, which is a manifestation of the Concorde fallacy and the sunk cost effect. Dawkins and Carlisle suggested that the reason the older offspring is preferred is not because of the magnitude of the prior investment, as Trivers had suggested, but because of the older offspring's need for less investment in the future. Consideration of the incremental benefits and costs, not of the sunk costs, compels the conclusion that the older offspring represents a far better investment for the parent to make.
Direct testing fails:
> A number of experimenters who have tested lower animals have confirmed that they simply do not succumb to the fallacy (see, e.g., [Armstrong & Robertson, 1988](/docs/sunkcosts/1988-armstrong.pdf); [Burger et al., 1989](/docs/sunkcosts/1989-burger.pdf); [Maestripieri & Alleva, 1991](/docs/sunkcosts/1991-maestripieri.pdf); [Wiklund, 1990](/docs/sunkcosts/1990-wiklund-b.pdf)[^Radford]).
[^Radford]: See also Radford & Blakey 2000, ["Intensity of nest defence is related to offspring sex ratio in the great tit _Parus major_"](http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1690574/pdf/10787154.pdf):
> Nest-defence behaviour of passerines is a form of parental investment. Parents are selected, therefore, to vary the intensity of their nest defence with respect to the value of their offspring. Great tit, _Parus major_, males were tested for their defence response to both a nest predator and playback of a great tit chick distress call. The results from the two trials were similar; males gave more alarm calls and made more perch changes if they had larger broods and if they had a greater proportion of sons in their brood. This is the first evidence for a relationship between nest-defence intensity and offspring sex ratio. Paternal quality, size, age and condition, lay date and chick condition did not significantly influence any of the measured nest-defence parameters.
>
> ...The most consistent pattern found in studies of avian nest defence has been an increase in the level of the parental response to predators from clutch initiation to £edging (e.g. [Biermann & Robertson 1981](/docs/sunkcosts/1981-biermann.pdf); [Regelmann & Curio 1983](/docs/sunkcosts/1983-regelmann.pdf); [Montgomerie & Weatherhead 1988](/docs/sunkcosts/1988-montgomerie.pdf); [Wiklund 1990 _a_](/docs/sunkcosts/1990-wiklund-a.pdf)). This supports the prediction from parental investment theory (Trivers 1972) that parents should risk more in defence of young that are more valuable to them. The intensity of nest defence is also expected to be positively correlated with brood size because the benefits of deterring a predator will increase with offspring number (Williams 1966; Wiklund 1990 _b_).
A direct example of the Trivers vs Dawkins & Carlisle argument:
> A prototypical study is that of Maestripieri and Alleva [1991], who tested the litter defense behavior of female albino mice. On the 8th day of a mother's lactation period, a male intruder was introduced to four different groups of mother mice and their litters. Each litter of the first group had been culled at birth to four pups. Each litter of the second group had been culled at birth to eight pups. In the third group, the litters had been culled at birth to eight pups, but four additional pups had been removed 3 to 4 hr before the intruder was introduced. The fourth group was identical to the third except that the removed pups had been returned to the litter after only a 10-min absence.
>
> The logic of the Maestripieri and Alleva (1991) study is straightforward. If each mother attended to past investment, then those litters that had eight pups during the prior 8 days should be defended most vigorously, as opposed to those litters that had only four pups. After all, having cared for eight pups represents a larger past investment than having cared for only four. On the other hand, if each mother attended to future costs and benefits, then those litters that had eight pups at the time of testing should be defended most vigorously, as opposed to those litters that had only four pups. The results were that the mothers with eight pups at the time of testing defended their litters more vigorously than did the mothers with four pups at the time of testing. The two groups of mothers with four pups did not differ in their level of aggression toward the intruder, even though one group of mothers had invested twice the energy in raising the young because they initially had to care for litters of eight pups.
Arkes & Ayton rebut 3 studies by arguing:
1. [Dawkins & Brockmann 1980](/docs/sunkcosts/1980-dawkins.pdf "Do digger wasps commit the Concorde fallacy?"): digger wasps fight harder in proportion to how much food they contributed, rather than the total - because they are too stupid to count the total and only know how much they personally collected & stand to lose
2. [Lavery 1995](/docs/sunkcosts/1995-lavery.pdf): cichlid fish successful in breeding also fight harder against predators; because this may reflect an intrinsic greater healthiness and greater future opportunities, rather than sunk cost fallacy, an argument similar to Northcraft & Wolfe 1984's criticism of apparent sunk costs in economics[^Northcraft]
3. [Weatherhead 1979](/docs/sunkcosts/1979-weatherhead.pdf): savannah sparrows defend their nests fiercer as the nest approaches hatching; because as already pointed out, the closer to hatching, the less future investment is required for X chicks compared to starting all over
4. To which 3 we may add tundra swan feeding habits, which are predicted to be optimal by [Pavlic & Passino 2011](http://pubs.tedpavlic.com/PavlicPassino11a.pdf "The Sunk-cost Effect as an Optimal Rate-maximizing Behavior")[^Pavlic], who remark "we show how optimization of Eq. 3 predicts the sunk-cost effect for certain scenarios; a common element of every case is a large initial cost."
[^Pavlic]: The swans:
> Although none of these terms are used, the same phenomena is also observed by [Nolet et al. (2001)](/docs/sunkcosts/2001-nolet.pdf "Spatial variation in tuber depletion by swans explained by differences in net intake rates"). In particular, tundra swans must expend more energy to "up-end" to feed on deep-water tuber patches than they do to "head-dip" to feed on shallow-water patches; however, contrary to the expectations of Nolet et al., the swans feed for a longer time on each high-cost deep-water patch. In every context, the observation of the sunk-cost effect is an enigma because intuition suggests that this behavior is suboptimal. Here, we show how optimization of Eq. (3) predicts the sunk-cost effect for certain scenarios; a common element of every case is a large initial cost.
[^Northcraft]: Northcraft, G., & Wolf, G. (1984). ["Dollars, sense, and sunk costs: A lifecycle model of research allocation decisions"](/docs/sunkcosts/1984-northcraft.pdf). _Academy of Management Review_, 9, 225-234:
> The decision maker also may treat the negative feedback as simply a learning experience-a cue to redirect efforts within a project rather than abandon it (Connolly, 1976).
>
> ...In some cases (Brockner, Shaw, & Rubin, 1979), the expected rate of return for further financial commitment even can be shown with a few assumptions to be increasing and (after a certain amount of investment) financially advisable, despite the claim that further resource commitment under the circumstances is psychologically rather than economically motivated....More to the point, the life cycle model clearly reveals the psychologist's fallacy: continuing a project in the face of a financial setback is not always irrational (it depends on the stage in the project and the magnitude of the financial setback). Second, the life cycle model provides an insight into the manager's preoccupation with a project's financial past. It demonstrates how a project's financial past can be used heuristically to understand the project's future.
Friedman et al 2006:
> ...There are also several possible rational explanations for an apparent concern with sunk costs. Maintaining a reputation for finishing what you start may have sufficient value to compensate for the expected loss on an additional investment. The '[real option](!Wikipedia)' value (e.g., Dixit and Pindyck, 1994 [_Investment Under Uncertainty_]) [cf. [O'Brien & Folta 2009](http://homepages.rpi.edu/~obriej8/Res/ICC09.pdf "Sunk costs, uncertainty and market exit: A real options perspective"), Tiwana & Fichman (2006)] of continuing a project also may offset an expected loss. [Agency problems](!Wikipedia) in organizations may make it personally better for a manager to continue an unprofitable project than to cancel it and take the heat from its supporters (e.g., Milgrom and Roberts, 1992 [_Economics, Organization, and Management_]).
One may ask why capital constraints aren't solved - if the projects really are good profitable ideas - by resort to equity or debt? But those are always last resorts due to fundamental coordination & trust issues; McAfee et al 2007:
> Abundant theoretical literature in corporate finance shows that imposing financial constraints on firm managers improves [agency problems](!Wikipedia) (see Stiglitz and Weiss, 1981, Myers and Majluf, 1984, Lewis and Sappington, 1989, and Hart and Moore, 1995). The theoretical conclusion finds overwhelming empirical support, and only a small fraction of business investment is funded by borrowing (see Fazzari and Athey, 1987, Fazzari and Peterson, 1993, and Love, 2003). When managers face financial constraints, sunk costs must influence firm investments simply because of budgets...Firms with financial constraints might rationally react to sunk costs by investing more in a project, rather than less, because the ability to undertake alternative investments declines in the level of sunk costs...Given limited resources, if the firm has already sunk more resources into the current project, then the value of the option to start a new project if it arises is lower relative the value of the option to continue the current project, because fewer resources are left over to bring any new project to fruition, and more resources have already been spent to bring the current project to fruition. Therefore, the firm's incentive to continue investing in the current project is higher the more resources it has already sunk into the project.
>
> - Stiglitz, Joseph E. and Weiss, Andrew, 1981. "Credit Rationing in Markets with Imperfect Information", _American Economic Review_ 71, 393-410.
> - Myers, Stewart and Majluf, Nicholas S., 1984. "Corporate Financing and Investment Decisions when Firms Have Information that Investors Do Not Have," _Journal of Financial Economics_ 13, 187-221
> - Lewis, Tracy and Sappington, David E. M., 1989. "Countervailing Incentives in Agency Problems," _Journal of Economic Theory_ 49, 294-313
> - Hart, Oliver and Moore, John, 1995. "Debt and Seniority: An Analysis of the Role of Hard Claims in Constraining Management," _American Economic Review_ 85, 567-585
> - Fazzari, Steven and Athey, Michael J., 1987. "Asymmetric Information, Financing Constraints, and Investment," _Review of Economics and Statistics_ 69, 481-487.
> - Fazzari, Steven and Petersen, Bruce, 1993. "Working Capital and Fixed Investment: New Evidence on Financing Constraints," _RAND Journal of Economics_ 24, 328-342
> - Love, Inessa, 2003. "Financial Development and Financing Constraints: International Evidence from the Structural Investment Model," _Review of Financial Studies_ 16, 765-791
(Navarro & Fantino 2004, ["The Sunk Cost Effect In Pigeons And Humans"](http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1193697/), claim sunk cost effect in pigeons, but it's hard to compare its strength to sunk cost in humans, and the setup is complex enough I'm not sure it is sunk cost.)
# Humans
## Children
Arkes & Ayton cite 2 studies finding that committing sunk cost bias increases with age - as in, children do not commit it. They also cite 2 studies saying that
> [Webley and Plaisier (1997)](http://www.wwwords.co.uk/pdf/freetoview.asp?j=csee&vol=3&issue=2&year=1998&article=1_Webley_CSEE_3_2_web) tested children at three different age groups (5-6, 8-9, and 11-12) with the following modification of the Tversky and Kahneman (1981) experiment ...the older children provided data analogous to those found by Tversky and Kahneman (1981): When the money was lost, the majority of the respondents decided to buy a ticket. On the other hand, when the ticket was lost, the majority decided not to buy another ticket. This difference was absent in the youngest children. Note that it is not the case that the youngest children were responding randomly. They showed a definite preference for purchasing a new ticket whether the money or the ticket had been lost. Like the animals that appear to be immune to the Concorde fallacy, young children seemed to be less susceptible than older children to this variant of the sunk cost effect. The results of the study by [Krouse (1986)](/docs/sunkcosts/1986-krouse.pdf) corroborate this finding: Compared with adult humans, young children, like animals, seem to be less susceptible to the Concorde fallacy/sunk cost effect.
>
> .... Perhaps the impulsiveness of young children (Mischel, Shoda, & Rodriguez, 1989) fostered their desire to buy a ticket for the merry-go-round right away, regardless of whether a ticket or money had been lost. However, this alternative interpretation does not explain why the younger children said that they would buy the ticket less often than the older children in the lost-money condition. Nor does this explanation explain the greater adherence to normative rules of decision making by younger children compared with adults in cases where impulsiveness is not an issue (see, e.g., [Jacobs & Potenza, 1991](/docs/sunkcosts/1991-jacobs.pdf); [Reyna & Ellis, 1994](/docs/sunkcosts/1994-reyna.pdf)).
I thinks Arkes & Ayton are probably wrong about children. Those 2 early studies can be criticized easily[^Klaczynski-criticism], and other studies point the opposite way. [Baron et al 1993](http://www.sas.upenn.edu/~baron/papers/kdm.pdf "Decision-making biases in children and early adolescents: Exploratory studies") asked poor and rich kids (age 5-12) questions including an Arkes & Blumer 1985 question, and found, in their first study no difference by age, ~30% of the 101 kids committing sunk cost and another ~30% unsure; in their second, they asked 2 questions, with ~50% committing sunk cost - and responses on the 2 questions minimally correlated (_r_=.17). [Klaczynski & Cottrell 2004](/docs/sunkcosts/2004-klaczynski.pdf) found that correct (non-sunk cost) responses went up with age (age 5-12, 16%; 5-16, 27%; and adults 37%). Bruine de Bruin et al 2007 found older adults more susceptible than young adults to some tested fallacies, but that sunk cost resistance increased somewhat with age. [Strough et al 2008](http://jonell_strough.psychology.wvu.edu/r/download/77072) studied 75 college age students, finding small or non-significant results for IQ (as did other studies, see later), education, and age; still older adults (60+) beat their college-age peers at avoiding sunk cost in both [Strough et al 2008](http://jonell_strough.psychology.wvu.edu/r/download/77072) & [Strough et al 2011](http://jonell_strough.psychology.wvu.edu/r/download/94125).
[^Klaczynski-criticism]: Klaczynski & Cottrell 2004:
> Although considerable evidence indicates that adults commit the SC fallacy frequently, age differences in the propensity to honour sunk costs have been little studied. In their investigations of 7-15-year-olds (Study 1) and 5-12-year-olds (Study 2), Baron et al. (1993) found no relationship between age and SC decisions. By contrast, [Klaczynski (2001b)](/docs/sunkcosts/2001-klaczynski.pdf) reported that the SC fallacy decreased from early adolescence to adulthood, although normative decisions were infrequent across ages. A third pattern of findings is reviewed by Arkes and Ayton (1999). Specifically, Arkes and Ayton argue that two studies (Krouse, 1986; Webley & Plaiser, 1998) indicate that younger children commit the SC fallacy less frequently than older children. Making sense of these conflicting findings is difficult because criticisms can be levied against each investigation. For instance, Arkes and Ayton (1999) questioned the null findings of Baron et al. (1993) because sample sizes were small (e.g., in Baron et al., Study 2, _n_ per age group ranged from 7 to 17). The problems used by Krouse (1986) and Webley and Plaiser (1998) were not, strictly speaking, SC problems (rather, they were problems of 'mental accounting'; see Webley & Plaiser, 1998). Because Klaczynski (2001b) did not include children in his sample, the age trends he reported are limited to adolescence. Thus, an interpretable montage of age trends in SC decisions cannot be created from prior research.
>
> ...An alternative proposition is based on the previously outlined theory of the role of metacognition in mediating interactions between analytic and heuristic processing. In this view, even young children have had ample opportunities to convert the 'waste not' heuristic from a conscious strategy to an automatically activated heuristic stored as a procedural memory. Evidence from children's experiences with food (e.g., Birch, Fisher, & Grimm-Thomas, 1999) provides some support for the argument that even preschoolers are frequently reinforced for not 'wasting' food. Mothers commonly extort their children to 'clean up their plates' even though they are sated and even though the nutritional effects of eating more than their bodies require are generally negative. If the 'waste not' heuristic is automatically activated in sunk cost situations for both children and adults, then one possibility is that no age differences in committing the fallacy should be expected. However, if activated heuristics are momentarily available for evaluation in working memory, then the superior metacognitive abilities of adolescents and adults should allow them to intercede in experiential processing before the heuristic is actually used. Although the evidence is clear that most adults do not take advantage of this opportunity for evaluation, the proportion of adolescents and adults who actively inhibit the 'waste not' heuristic should be greater than the same proportion of children.
(Children also violate [transitivity of choices](http://pubs.aeaweb.org/doi/pdfplus/10.1257/aer.91.5.1539 "Harbaugh, Krause, Berry 2001 'GARP for Kids: on the development of rational choice behavior'") & are more hyperbolic than adults, which is hardly normative.[^children-hyperbolic])
[^children-hyperbolic]: eg. ["Discounting of Delayed Rewards: A Life-Span Comparison"](http://psych.wustl.edu/lengreen/publications/Discounting%20of%20delayed%20rewards%20(1994).pdf), Green et al 1994; abstract:
> In this study, children, young adults, and older adults chose between immediate and delayed hypothetical monetary rewards. The amount of the delayed reward was held constant while its delay was varied. All three age groups showed delay discounting; that is, the amount of an immediate reward judged to be of equal value to the delayed reward decreased as a function of delay. The rate of discounting was highest for children and lowest for older adults, predicting a life-span developmental trend toward increased self-control. Discounting of delayed rewards by all three age groups was well described by a single function with age-sensitive parameters (all R^2^s > .94). Thus, even though there are quantitative age differences in delay discounting, the existence of an age-invariant form of discount function suggests that the process of choosing between rewards of different amounts and delays is qualitatively similar across the life span.
## Uses
### Learning & Memory
> 18\. "If the fool would persist in his folly he would become wise."
>
> 46\. "You never know what is enough unless you know what is more than enough."^[[William Blake](!Wikipedia), ["Proverbs of Hell"](http://interglacial.com/~sburke/pub/prose/Blake_-_Proverbs_of_Hell.html)]
Felix Hoeffler in his 2008 paper ["Why humans care about sunk costs while (lower) animals don't: An evolutionary explanation"](http://www.coll.mpg.de/download/Hoeffler/Sunk%20Cost_080331.pdf) takes the previous points at face values and asks how sunk cost might be useful for humans; his answer is that sunk cost forfeits some total gains/utility - just as our simple model indicated - but in exchange for *faster learning*, an exchange motivated by humans' well-known [risk aversion](!Wikipedia) and dislike of uncertainty[^uncertainty]. It is harder to learn the value of choices if one is constantly breaking off before completion to make other choices, or realize any value at all (the classic [exploration vs exploitation](!Wikipedia "Multi-armed bandit") problem, amusingly illustrated in [Clarke](!Wikipedia "Arthur C. Clarke")'s story ["Superiority"](http://www.mayofamily.com/RLM/txt_Clarke_Superiority.html)).
[^uncertainty]: ["The Bias Against Creativity: Why People Desire But Reject Creative Ideas"](http://digitalcommons.ilr.cornell.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1457&context=articles), Mueller et al 2011:
> Uncertainty is an aversive state (Fiske & Taylor, 1991 [_Social cognition_]; Heider, 1958 [_The psychology of interpersonal relations_]) which people feel a strong motivation to diminish and avoid ([Whitson & Galinsky, 2008](http://rifters.com/real/articles/Science_LackingControlIncreasesIllusoryPatternPerception.pdf)).
One could imagine a not too intelligent program which is, like humans, over-optimistic about the value of new projects; it always chooses the highest value option, of course, to avoid committing sunk cost bias, but oddly enough, it never seems to finish projects because better opportunities seem to keep coming along... In the real world, learning is valuable and one has many reasons to persevere even past the point one regards a decision as a mistake; McAfee et al 2007 (remember the exponential vs hyperbolic discounting example):
> Consider a project that may take an unknown expenditure to complete. The failure to complete the project with a given amount of investment is informative about the expected amount needed to complete it. Therefore, the expected additional investment required for fruition will be correlated with the sunk investment. Moreover, in a world of random returns, the realization of a return is informative about the expected value of continuing a project. A large loss, which leads to a rational inference of a high variance, will often lead to a higher option value because option values tend to rise with variance. Consequently, the informativeness of sunk investments is amplified by consideration of the option value...Moreover, given limited time to invest in projects, as the time remaining shrinks, individuals have less time over which to amortize their costs of experimenting with new projects, and therefore may be rationally less likely to abandon current projects...Past investments in a given course of action often provide evidence about whether the course of action is likely to succeed or fail in the future. Other things equal, a greater investment usually implies that success is closer at hand. Consider the following simple model...The only case in which the size of the sunk investment cannot affect the firm's rational decision about whether to continue investing is the rather special case in which the hazard is exactly constant.
If this model is applicable to humans, we would expect to see a cluster of results related to age, learning, teaching, difficulty of avoiding even with training or education, minimal avoidance with greater intelligence, completion of tasks/projects, largeness of sums (the risks most worth avoiding), and competitiveness of environment. (As well as occasional null results like [Elliott & Curme 2006](http://www.fsb.muohio.edu/fsb/ecopapers/docs/elliotsr-2006-09-paper.pdf "'Understanding the Sunk Cost Effect: An Experimental Approach', Elliott & Curme 2006").) And we do! Many otherwise anomalous results snap into focus with this suggestion:
1. information is worth most to those who have the least: as we [previously saw](#children), the young commit sunk cost more than the old
2. in situations where participants can learn and update, we should expect sunk cost to be attenuated or disappear; we do see this (eg. Friedman et al 2006[^Friedman-updating], [Garland et al 1990](/docs/sunkcosts/1990-garland.pdf)[^Garland-1990], Bornstein et al 1999[^Bornstein-1999], Staw 1981[^Staw-1981-learning], McCain 1986[^McCain], Phillips et al 1991[^Phillips], [Wang & Xu 2012](http://www.economics.neu.edu/zwang/Penny%20auction.pdf "Learning and Strategic Sophistication in Games: The Case of Penny Auctions on the Internet")[^penny-auctions])
3. the noisier (higher variance) feedback on profitability was, the more data it took before people give up ([Bragger et al 1998](/docs/sunkcosts/1998-bragger.pdf "Hysteresis and Uncertainty: The Effect of Uncertainty on Delays to Exit Decisions"), [Bragger et al 2003](/docs/sunkcosts/2003-bragger.pdf "When success breeds failure: History, hysteresis, and delayed exit decisions"))
4. sunk costs were supported more when subjects were given justifications about learning to make better decisions or whether teachers/students were involved (Bornstein & Chapman 1995[^Bornstein-1995])
5. extensive economic training does not stop economics professors from committing sunk cost, and students can be quickly educated to answer sunk cost questions correctly, but with little carry-through to their lives[^Larrick], and researchers in the area argue about whether particular setups even represent sunk costs at all, on their own merits[^Brockner-1985] (but don't feel smug, you probably wouldn't do much better if you took [quizzes](http://messymatters.com/2009/06/23/sunk/) [on it](http://lesswrong.com/lw/9hb/position_design_and_write_rationality_curriculum/) either)
6. when measured, avoiding sunk cost has little correlation with intelligence[^Stanovich] - and one wonders how much of the correlation comes from intelligent people being more likely to try to conform to what they have learned is economics orthodoxy
7. a 'nearly completed' effect dominates 'sunk cost' ([Conlon & Garland 1993](/docs/sunkcosts/1993-conlon.pdf), [Garland & Conlon 1998](/docs/sunkcosts/1998-garland.pdf), [Boehne & Paese 2002](/docs/sunkcosts/2002-boehne.pdf), [Fontino et al 2007](http://books.google.com/books?id=kuD6LHknaLUC "'Multiple Causes of the Sunk Cost Effect', in _Psychology of decision making in legal, health care and science settings_"))
8. for example, the larger the proportion, the more costs were sunk ([Garland & Newport 1991](/docs/sunkcosts/1991-garland.pdf))
9. it is surprisingly hard to find clear-cut real-world non-government examples of serious sunk costs; the commonly cited non-historical examples do not stack up:
- Staw & Hoang 1995[^Hoang] studied the NBA to see whether high-ranked but underperforming players were over-used by coaches, a sunk cost.
Unfortunately, they do not track the over-use down to actual effects on win-loss or other measures of team performance, effects which are unlikely to be very large since the overuse amounts to ~10-20 minutes a game. Further, ["The econometrics and behavioral economics of escalation of commitment: a re-examination of Staw and Hoang's NBA data"](http://authors.library.caltech.edu/22085/1/wp1043%5B1%5D.pdf) (Camerer & Weber 1999), claims to do a better analysis of the NBA data and find the effect is actually weaker. As usual, there are multiple alternatives^[Friedman et al 2006: "...Of course, it is hard to completely rule out other explanations based on unobserved components of performance or the coaches' Bayesian priors."].
- McCarthy et al 1993[^McCarthy] is a much-cited correlational study finding that small entrepreneurs invest further in companies they founded (rather than bought) when the company apparently does poorly; but they acknowledge that there are financial strategies clouding the data, and like Staw & Hoang, do not tie the small effect - which appears only for a year or two, as the entrepreneurs apparently learn - to actual negative outcomes or decrease in expected value.
- similar to McCarthy et al 1993, Wennberg et al 2009[^Wennberg] tracked 'exit routes' for young companies such as being bought, merged, or bankrupt - but again, they did not tie apparent sunk cost to *actual* poor performance.
- in 2 studies[^Africa], Africans did not engage in sunk cost with insecticide-treated bed nets - whether they paid a subsidized price or got them for free did not affect use levels, and in one study, this null effect happened despite the same household engaging in sunk cost for hypothetical questions
- Internet users may commit sunk cost in browsing news websites[^Friedman-internet] (but is that very serious?)
- an unpublished 2001 paper (Barron et al "The Escalation Phenomenon and Executive Turnover: Theory and Evidence") reportedly finds that projects are 'significantly more likely' to be canceled when their top managers leave, suggesting a sunk cost effect of substantial size; but it is unclear how much money is at stake or whether this is - remember point #1 - power politics[^Barron]
- sunk cost only weakly correlates with suboptimal behavior (much less demonstrates causation):
[Parker & Fischhoff 2005](http://web.archive.org/web/20121207093452/http://sds.hss.cmu.edu/media/pdfs/fischhoff/Parker_FischhoffDMC.pdf "Decision-making competence: External validation through an individual-differences approach") and [Bruine de Bruin et al 2007](http://web.archive.org/web/20111109053537/http://www.hss.cmu.edu/departments/sds/media/pdfs/fischhoff/ADMC-JPSP2007.pdf "Individual Differences in Adult Decision-Making Competence") compiled a number of questions for several cognitive biases - including sunk cost - and then asked questions about impulsiveness, number of sexual partners, etc, while the latter developed a 34-item index of bad decisions/outcomes (the DOI): ever rent a movie you didn't watch, get expelled, file for bankruptcy, forfeit your driver's license, miss an airplane, bounce a check, etc. Then they ran correlations. They replicated the minimal correlation of sunk cost avoidance with IQ, but sunk cost (and 'path independence') exhibited fascinating behaviors compared to the other biases/fallacies measured: sunk cost & path independence correlated minimally with the *other* tested biases/fallacies, [Cronbach's alpha](!Wikipedia)s were almost uselessly low, education did not help much, age helped some, and sunk cost had low correlations with the risky behavior or the DOI (eg. after controlling for decision-making styles, 0.13).
- [Larrick et al 1993](http://deepblue.lib.umich.edu/bitstream/2027.42/30415/1/0000035.pdf "Who uses the cost-benefit rules of choice? Implications for the normative status of microeconomic theory") found tests of normative economic reasoning, including sunk cost questions, correlated with increased academic salaries, even for non-economic professors like biologists & humanists (but the effect size & causality are unclear)
10. Dissociation in hypotheticals - being told a prior manager made decisions - does not always counteract effects ([Biyalogorsky 2006](http://portal.idc.ac.il/FacultyPublication.Publication?PublicationID=626&FacultyUserName=ZWJpYWxvZ29yc2t5 "Stuck in the past: Why managers persist with new product failures"))
[^penny-auctions]: In particular, "Pay-to-bid" [penny auction](!Wikipedia)s such as [Swoopo](!Wikipedia) have been called [instances of sunk cost fallacy](http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/the-decision-lab/201110/ipad-1495-sunk-cost-fallacy-and-why-people-keep-losing-money-in-penny-a "An iPad for $14.95? Sunk Cost Fallacy and Why People Keep Losing Money in Penny Auctions"), or "escalation of commitment" by no less than [Richard H. Thaler](http://www.nytimes.com/2009/11/15/business/economy/15view.html "Paying a Price for the Thrill of the Hunt"), and described by techie [Jeff Atwood](!Wikipedia) as being ["as close to pure, distilled evil in a business plan as I've ever seen"](http://www.codinghorror.com/blog/2008/12/profitable-until-deemed-illegal.html "Profitable Until Deemed Illegal"). But as [Wang & Xu 2012](http://www.economics.neu.edu/zwang/Penny%20auction.pdf "Learning and Strategic Sophistication in Games: The Case of Penny Auctions on the Internet") and [Caldara 2012](http://www.chapman.edu/research-and-institutions/economic-science-institute/_files/BrownBag/michaelcaldera2012.pdf "Bidding Behavior in Pay-to-Bid Auctions: An Experimental Study") indicate, while people do lose money to the penny auctions, they eventually *do* learn that penny auctions are not good ideas and escape the trap. A previous analysis of penny auctions, [Augenblick 2009](http://faculty.haas.berkeley.edu/ned/Penny_Auction.pdf "Consumer and Producer Behavior in the Market for Penny Auctions: A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis"), omitted detailed survivorship data but still found some learning effects. And indeed, Swoopo has since shut down.
[^Stanovich]: The previously mentioned studies of sunk cost in children found minimal correlations with intelligence, when that was measured. For adults, see Strough et al 2008, previously cited. Also, Stanovich, K. E., & West, R. F. (2008b). ["On the relative independence of thinking biases and cognitive ability"](http://www.keithstanovich.com/Site/Research_on_Reasoning_files/JPSP08.pdf). _Journal of Personality and Social Psychology_, 94, 672-695 (pg 7-8):
> Both cognitive ability groups displayed sunk-cost effects of roughly equal magnitude. For the high-SAT group, the mean in the no-sunk-cost condition was 6.90 and the mean in the sunk-cost condition was 5.08, whereas for the low-SAT group, the mean in the no-sunk-cost condition was 6.50 and the mean in the sunk-cost condition was 4.19. A 2 (cognitive ability) ϫ 2 (condition) [ANOVA](!Wikipedia) indicated a significant main effect of cognitive ability, F(1, 725) ϭ 8.40, MSE ϭ 9.13, p Ͻ .01, and a significant main effect of condition, F(1, 725) ϭ 84.9, MSE ϭ 9.13, p Ͻ .001. There was a slight tendency for the low-SAT participants to show a larger sunk-cost effect, but the Cognitive Ability ϫ Condition interaction did not attain statistical significance, F(1, 725) ϭ 1.21, MSE ϭ 9.13. The interaction was also tested in a regression analyses in which SAT was treated as a continuous variable rather than as a dichotomous variable. The Form ϫ SAT cross product, when entered third in the equation, was not significant, F(1, 725) ϭ 0.32.
>
> The sunk-cost effect thus represents another cognitive bias that is not strongly attenuated by cognitive ability. However, this is true only when it is assessed in a between-subjects context. Using a similar sunk-cost problem, [Stanovich & West 1999](/docs/sunkcosts/1999-stanovich.pdf "Discrepancies Between Normative and Descriptive Models of Decision Making and the Understanding/Acceptance Principle") did find an association with cognitive ability when participants responded in a within-subjects design.
And Parker & Fischhoff 2005:
> The first two rows of Table 5 show strong correlations between five of the seven DMC component measures and respondents' scores on the WISC-R vocabulary test and on Giancola et al.'s (1996) measure of ECF. Consistency in risk perception and resistance to sunk cost show little relationship to either of these general cognitive abilities.^8,9^ [correlations: 0.12, 0.08]
Bruine de Bruin et al 2007, modifying Parker & Fischhoff 2005's test battery, improved the consistency of the sunk cost questions, and found similar small correlations with their 2 IQ measures, of 0.17 and 0.04. Larrick et al 1993 recorded SAT/ACT scores (close proxies for IQ) and found some correlation, and noted that IQ was "positively related to recognition of economists' position on various economic problems."
[^Friedman-updating]: ["Searching for the Sunk Cost Fallacy"](http://128.118.178.162/eps/exp/papers/0407/0407008.pdf), Friedman et al 2006:
> Subjects play a computer game in which they decide whether to keep digging for treasure on an island or to sink a cost (which will turn out to be either high or low) to move to another island. The research hypothesis is that subjects will stay longer on islands that were more costly to find. Nine treatment variables are considered, e.g. alternative visual displays, whether the treasure value of an island is shown on arrival or discovered by trial and error, and alternative parameters for sunk costs. The data reveal a surprisingly small and erratic sunk cost effect that is generally insensitive to the proposed psychological drivers.
I cite Friedman 2006 here so much because it's unusual - as McAfee et al 2007 puts it:
> ...Most of the existing empirical work has not controlled for changing hazards, option values, reputations for ability and commitment, and budget constraints. We are aware of only one study in which several of these factors are eliminated - Friedman et al. (2006). In an experimental environment without option value or reputation considerations, the authors find only very small and statistically insignificant sunk cost effects in the majority of their treatments, consistent with the rational theory presented here.
[^Hoang]: ["Sunk Costs in the NBA: Why Draft Order Affects Playing Time and Survival in Professional Basketball"](/docs/sunkcosts/1995-hoang.pdf):
> A second problem is that much of the escalation literature, despite its intent to sources of commitment, has not directly explain nonrational challenged the assumptions of economic decision making. By and large, the escalation literature has demonstrated that psychological and social factors *can* influence resource allocation decisions, not that the rational assumptions of decision making are in error. A third weakness is that almost all the escalation literature is laboratory based. Aside from a few recent qualitative case studies (e.g., Ross and Staw, 1986, 1993), escalation predictions have not been confirmed settings, using data that are or falsified in real organizational generated in their natural context. Therefore, despite the size of the escalation literature, it is still uncertain if to escalation effects can be generalized from the laboratory the field.
>
> ...Garland, Sandefur, and Rogers (1990) found a similar absence of sunk-cost effects in an experiment using an oil-drilling scenario. Prior expenditures on dry wells were not associated with continued drilling, perhaps because dry wells were so clearly seen as reducing rather than increasing the likelihood of future oil production. Thus it appears that sunk costs may only be influential on project decisions when they are linked to the perception (if not the reality) of progress on a course of action.
>
> ...Table 2 also shows that draft order was a significant predictor of minutes played over the entire five-year period. This effect was above and beyond any effects of a player's performance, injury, or trade status. The regressions showed that every increment in the draft number decreased playing time by as much as 23 minutes in the second year (I, = -22.77, p < .001, one-tailed test). Likewise, being taken in the second rather than the first round of the draft meant 552 minutes less playing time during a player's second year in the NBA.
[^McCarthy]: ["Reinvestment decisions by entrepreneurs: Rational decision-making or escalation of commitment?"](/docs/sunkcosts/1993-mccarthy.pdf), McCarthy et al 1993:
> The hypotheses were tested using data from a longitudinal study involving 1112 firms. It was found that entrepreneurs who had started their firms and those who had expressed substantial over-confidence were significantly more likely to make the decision to expand. The hypotheses that those who had partners and those who expected to apply their skills would be more likely to expand were not supported. Furthermore, and consistent with previous research, these psychological escalation predictors seemed to exert a greater influence when feedback from the marketplace was negative. As expected, there was a declining influence in the third year as compared with the second. Consistent with the prior literature and the hypotheses, these psychological predictors did show a small, but systematic influence upon reinvestment decisions.
>
> ...Although the hypothesis regarding PARTNR was not supported, as noted, the zero-order correlation between PARTNR and NEWCAP2 is in the predicted direction (r = .06, p < .05, one-tailed). Thus, entrepreneurs with partners may be more likely to expand the asset base of their firms than they would be if they were sole owners. This has significant implications for entrepreneurial teams, in that the presence of partners does not inhibit the tendency to escalate, but in fact increases that tendency. This means that having partners is not insurance against the tendency to escalate. This is consistent with the research on escalation (Bazerman et al. 1984).
>
> ...A puzzling finding was the lack of any relationship between financial indicators from the previous year and new capital invested in the business. In other words, there was no systematic relationship between sales growth and expansion of the asset base for these young firms. This may mean that many of these firms started with some excess capacity so that it was not necessary to add to facilities to support their early growth. It may also mean that management of working capital was erratic. On the other hand. the psychological factors predicted by escalation theory did, in two of four cases, show systematic relationships to additional investment.
>
> ...One final issue worth comment is the relatively small amount of variance accounted for by the models described in this study. The variance accounted for in this research is in line with the findings in similar studies of escalation. In a recent field study of the escalation bias, Schoorman (1988) reported that the escalation bias accounted for 6% of the variance in performance ratings. Schoorman (1988) noted in this article that the escalation variables were more powerful predictors of performance (at 6%) than a measure of ability used in a validated selection test for these same employees....Taken together these findings provide support for the view that escalation bias is a significant and common problem in decision-making among entrepreneurs. The characteristics of entrepreneurs and the nature of the decisions they are required to make leave them particularly vulnerable to escalation bias. Efforts to train entrepreneurs to guard against this bias may be very valuable.
[^Wennberg]: ["Reconceptualizing entrepreneurial exit: Divergent exit routes and their drivers"](http://www.business.uconn.edu/ccei/files/IDEAawards/Cardon.PDF), Wennberg et al 2009:
> ...An alternative failure-avoidance strategy is to invest additional equity. We found that such reinvestments reduced the probability of all exit routes. While previous research on reinvestment also found that reinvestment was not related to well-defined performance levels (McCarthy et al., 1993), it is interesting that it also reduced the odds of harvest sales and harvest liquidations. As a failure-avoidance strategy, reinvestment thus seems to be less effective than cost reduction. Cost reductions have direct effects on firm performance while reinvestments provide a temporary buffer for failing firms. As suggested, there might be disincentives to additional investments if tax laws punish entrepreneurs taking out money as salaries or dividends. If corroborated, this is an important finding for public policy makers.
[^Bornstein-1995]: ["Learning lessons from sunk costs"](http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1293&context=psychfacpub), Bornstein & Chapman 1995:
> Study participants rated the quality of several arguments for continuing an original plan in sunk cost situations in order to (a) avoid wasting resources, (b) learn to make better decisions, (c) punish poor decision making, and (d) appear consistent. The lesson-learning argument was perceived as most appropriate when adult teachers taught lessons to others, the original decision was carelessly made, or if it consumed comparatively more resources. Ratings of the lesson-learning argument were higher for teacher-learner than for adult-alone situations, regardless of whether the learner was a child or an adult. The implications for improving decision making and judging whether the sunk cost effect is a bias are discussed....However, prospect theory does not predict an effect of variables such as whether the decision maker acted alone, the care with which the decision was made, or the nature of the relationship between teacher and learner. The other three responses were influenced by these variables.
>
> What appears to be a bias in the laboratory may be functional behavior in a more realistic context (Funder, 1987; Hogarth, 1981), where a variety of justifications for the behavior can be considered. In general, ignoring sunk costs is an adaptive, cost-effective strategy. Yet what appears to be biased, irrational behavior - such as decreasing utility through attention to irretrievably wasted resources - can be described as 'meta-rational' (Jungermann, 1986), assuming the benefits of learning and implementing the lesson outweigh the costs of sticking to the original plan. However, it raises the interesting question of why continuing a failed plan is the best (or even a good) way to learn to make better decisions in the future. Perhaps one could both abandon the current unsuccessful plan and learn to think more carefully in future decisions.
[^Africa]: See [Cohen & Dupas 2007](http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1080301) and [Ashraf et al 2007](http://www.hbs.edu/research/pdf/07-034.pdf); on the hypothetical (summary from [Holla & Kremer 2009](http://www.cgdev.org/files/1420826_file_Holla_Kremer_Health_#_Access.pdf), pg 11):
> When they divide their sample into households that displayed a sunk-cost effect when responding to a hypothetical scenario posed to them by surveyors and those that did not, they find coefficients of much larger magnitude for the hypothetical-sunk-cost households, although these remain insignificant and cannot be statistically distinguished from the estimated effects for households that did not display this hypothetical sunk-cost effect. Ashraf et al (2007) identify hypothetical-sunk-cost households from their answers to the following question posed during the follow-up survey: *Suppose you bought a bottle of juice for 1,000 Kw. When you start to drink it, you realize you don't really like the taste. Would you finish drinking it?*
[^Bornstein-1999]: [Bornstein et al. 1999](http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1211&context=psychfacpub "Rationality in medical treatment decisions: Is there a sunk-cost effect?"):
> Measurements and main results: Residents evaluated medical and non-medical situations that varied the amount of previous investment and whether the present decision maker was the same or different from the person who had made the initial investment. They rated reasons both for continuing the initial decision (e.g., stay with the medication already in use) and for switching to anew alternative (e.g., a different medication). There were two main findings: First, the residents' ratings of whether to continue or switch medical treatments were not influenced by the amount of the initial investment (p's > 0.05). Second, residents' reasoning was more normative in medical than in non-medical situations, in which it paralleled that of undergraduates (p's < 0.05).
>
> Conclusions: Medical residents' evaluation of treatment decisions reflected good reasoning, in that they were not influenced by the amount of time and/or money that had already been invested in treating a patient. However, the residents did demonstrate a sunk-cost effect in evaluating non-medical situations. Thus, any advantage in decision making that is conferred by medical training appears to be domain specific.
Some of this was replicated & generalized in [Braverman & Blumenthal-Barby 2012](/docs/sunkcosts/2012-braverman.pdf "Assessment of the sunk cost effect in clinical decision making"):
> Specifically, we surveyed 389 health care providers in a large urban medical center in the United States during August 2009. We asked participants to make a treatment recommendation based on one of four hypothetical clinical scenarios that varied in the source and type of prior investment described. By comparing recommendations across scenarios, we found that providers did not demonstrate a sunk-cost effect; rather, they demonstrated a significant tendency to over-compensate for the effect. In addition, we found that more than one in ten health care providers recommended continuation of an ineffective treatment.
[^Staw-1981-learning]: Staw 1981, ["The Escalation of Commitment to a Course of Action"](/docs/sunkcosts/1981-staw.pdf):
> ...However, when choosing to commit resources, subjects did not appear to persist unswervingly in the face of continued negative results or to ignore information about the possibility of future returns. These inconsistencies led to a third study [Staw & Ross, 1978] designed specifically to find out how individuals process information following negative versus positive feedback. In this third study, previous success/failure and causal information about a setback were both experimentally varied. Results showed that subjects invested more resources in a course of action when information pointed to an exogenous rather than endogenous cause of a setback, and this tendency was most pronounced when subjects had been given a previous failure rather than a success. The exogenous cause in this experiment was one that was both external to the program in which subjects invested and was unlikely to persist, where- as the endogenous cause was a problem central to the program and likely to persist.
[^McCain]: ["Continuing investment under conditions of failure: A laboratory study of the limits to escalation"](/docs/sunkcosts/1986-mccain.pdf), McCain 1986:
> [Brockner et al. (1982)](/docs/sunkcosts/1982-brockner.pdf), following Teger (1980), have also specifically suggested that entrapment involves two distinct stages. In the first stage subjects respond primarily to economic incentives, whereas self-justification supposedly governs the second. Brockner et al. found that cost salience significantly reduced entrapment early on but had little effect in later periods....Thus, a process that reflects efforts to *learn* both what caused the setbacks and the implications of that cause for future action may provide a better model of de-escalation.
>
> ...The findings of this study clearly showed that the escalation effect, defined by a difference between the allocations of high- and low-choice subjects, was limited to the initial stages of continuing investment. The findings were consistent with previous research ([Staw & Fox, 1977](http://hum.sagepub.com/content/30/5/431.full.pdf+html)) and support the contention that investment in failing projects involves two stages. Clearly, too, the availability of alternative investments limited the escalation effect. When subjects were given alternatives to the failing investment, the difference between the investments of the high- and low-choice groups disappeared. The results showed, as well, that high-choice subjects who displayed the escalation effect quit funding the failing investment sooner than comparable low-choice subjects, contrary to a commitment perspective. Similarly, the declining hazard rates observed here support a learning model more than they support the self-justification model...Some authors (e.g., [Northcraft & Wolf, 1984](/docs/sunkcosts/1984-northcraft.pdf)) have suggested that investors react differently to cost overruns than they react to revenue shortfalls, yet many escalation experiments do not clearly specify whether setbacks result from higher than expected costs or from lower than expected revenues. Clearly, if investors are sensitive to uncertainty, as the attributional model suggests, researchers must consider how subjects may respond to an inadequately specified investment context...
[^Larrick]: See Arkes & Blumer 1985, which found no resistance in students who had were taken an economics course and most of whom had taken other economics courses; also good is Larrick et al 1993 or [Larrick et al 1990](/docs/sunkcosts/1990-larrick.pdf), "Teaching the use of cost-benefit reasoning in everyday life":
> It may be seen in Table 1 that economists' reasoning on the university and international policy questions was more in line with cost-benefit rules than was that of biologists and humanists. This pattern was found for the net-benefit questions (p < .05), and for the opportunity cost questions (p < .05) and a trend was found for the sunk cost questions (p < .15)...Third, economists were more likely than biologists and humanists to report that they ignored sunk costs or attended to opportunity costs in their personal decisions. For instance, they were more likely to have dropped a research project because it was not proving worthwhile. (It is interesting to note that economists were not simply more likely to drop projects. All three disciplines gave the same answer on average to the question "have you ever dropped a research project because of a lack of funding?") Finally, economists participated in a greater number of time-saving activities...The results show that training people only briefly on an economic principle significantly alters their solutions to hypothetical economic problems [including sunk cost]. Moreover, training effects generalize fully from a financial domain to a nonfinancial one and vice versa...The means for both indices showed that [quick-economics] trained subjects were ignoring sunk costs more than untrained subjects, but only the nine-item index based on the question "Have you bought one of the following items at some time and then not used it in the past month" approached significance. Trained subjects reported that they had paid for but not used 1.14 objects and activities compared to .84 for untrained subjects, f(78) = 1.64, p = .10.
On the other hand, [Fennema & Perkins 2008](/docs/sunkcosts/2008-fennema.pdf "Mental Budgeting Versus Marginal Decision Making: Training, Experience and Justification Effects on Decisions Involving Sunk Costs"):
> The results indicate that practicing Certified Public Accountants (CPAs), Masters of Business Administration students (MBAs) and undergraduate accounting students perform better than undergraduate psychology students. The level of training, as measured by the number of college courses in managerial accounting, was found to be positively correlated with performance, while the level of experience, as measured by years of financially-related work, was not. Justification was found to improve decisions only for those participants with significant work experience (MBAs and CPAs). Strategies used in this type of decision were examined with the surprising finding that economically rational decisions can be made even if sunk costs are not ignored.
[^Friedman-internet]: Friedman et al 2006:
> Do Internet users respond to sunk time costs? [Manley & Seltzer (1997)](https://db.usenix.org/publications/library/proceedings/usits97/full_papers/manley/manley.pdf) report that after a particular website imposed an access charge, the remaining users stayed longer. A rival explanation to the sunk cost fallacy is selection bias: the users with shortest stays when the site was free are those who stopped coming when they had to pay. [Klein et al (1999)](http://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/download?doi=10.1.1.46.5864&rep=rep1&type=pdf) report that users stick around longer on their site after encountering delays while playing a game, but again selection bias is a possible alternative explanation. The issue is important in e-commerce because 'stickier' sites earn more advertising revenue. Schwartz (1999) [_Digital Darwinism: 7 Breakthrough Business Strategies for Surviving in the Cutthroat Web Economy_] reports that managers of the free _Wall Street Journal_ site deliberately slowed the login process in the belief that users would then stay longer. One of us (Lukose) took a sample of 2000 user logs from a website and found a significant positive correlation between residence time at the site and download latency. One alternative explanation is unobserved congestion on the web, and users may have been responding more to expected future time costs than to time costs already sunk. Also, good sites may be more popular because they are good, leading to (a) congestion and (b) more time spent on the site.
[^Barron]: Friedman et al 2006:
> ...Barron et al. (2001) find that US firms are significantly more likely to terminate projects following the departure of top managers. This might reflect the new managers' insensitivity to costs sunk by their predecessors, or it might simply reflect two aspects of the same broad realignment decision.
[^Phillips]: "Sunk and Opportunity Costs in Valuation and Bidding", [Phillips et al 1991](/docs/sunkcosts/1991-phillips.pdf), which also mentions another apparent instance of market agents initially committing sunk cost and then learning: Plott & Uhl 1981 "Competitive Equilibrium with Middlemen: An Empirical Study", _Southern Economic Journal_
[^Garland-1990]: On the lessons of Garland et al 1990's observation of *non* sunk cost fallacy, McAfee et al 2007:
> While some projects have an increasing hazard, others appear to have a decreasing hazard. For example, [curing cancer](!Wikipedia "War on Cancer"), originally expected to cost $1 billion (see Epstein, 1998), probably has a decreasing hazard; given initial failure, the odds of immediate success recede and the likely expenditures required to complete grow. Oil-exploration projects might also be characterized by decreasing hazards. Suppose a firm acquires a license to drill a number of wells in a fixed area. It decides to drill a well on a particular spot in the area. Suppose the well turns out to be dry. The costs of drilling the well are then sunk. But the dry well might indicate that the likelihood of striking oil on another spot in the area is low since the geophysical characteristics of surface rocks and terrain for the next spot are more or less the same as the ones for the previous spot that turned out to be dry. Thus, the firm might be rationally less likely to drill another well. In general, firms might be less willing to drill another well the more wells they had already found to be dry. This may in part explain the rapid "de-escalation" observed by Garland, Sandeford, and Rogers (1990) in their oil-exploration experiments.
[^Brockner-1985]: For example, [Heath 1995](http://faculty-gsb.stanford.edu/heath/documents/escalationanddeescalation.pdf "Escalation and de-escalation of commitment in response to sunk costs") spends a page criticizing Brockner & Rubin 1985's setup of endowed subjects buying tickets in a lottery, pointing out they took subjects quitting ticket purchases after a long run of ticket-buying as evidence of sunk cost, even though if the expected value of the lottery was positive, the normative rational strategy is for the subject spend every penny of the endowment buying tickets! "Consider, for example, the average of $3.82 invested in the game with a $10.00 prize. In this game, the average subject quits at a point where the expected benefits from a marginal investment are *three times* what they were when the subject began investing." [emphasis added]
Sunk costs may also reflect imperfect memory about what information one had in the past; one may reason that one's past self had better information about all the forgotten details that went into a decision to make some investments, and respect their decision, thus appearing to honor sunk costs ([Baliga & Ely 2011](http://www.kellogg.northwestern.edu/faculty/baliga/htm/Mnemonomics-%20The%20Sunk%20Cost%20Fallacy%20as%20a%20Memory%20Kludge.pdf "Mnemonomics: The Sunk Cost Fallacy as a Memory Kludge")).
### Countering hyperbolic discounting?
> "Use barbarians against barbarians"^[[Henry Kissinger](!Wikipedia), [_On China_](http://www.amazon.com/China-Henry-Kissinger/dp/0143121316/) 2011; a "traditional maxim" in Chinese statecraft]
The classic kicker of hyperbolic discounting is that it induces temporal discounting - your far-sighted self is able to calculate what *is* best for you, but then your near-sighted self screws it all up by changing tacks. Knowing this, it may be a good idea to *not* work on your 'bad' habit of being overconfident about your projects[^optimism] or engaging in planning fallacy, since at least they will counteract a little the hyperbolic discounting; in particular, you should distrust near-term estimates of the fun or value of activities when you have not learned anything very important[^hyperbolic-oppose]. We could run the same argument but instead point to the [psychology research on the connection between blood sugar levels and 'willpower'](DNB FAQ#fn53); if it takes willpower to start a project but little willpower to cease working on or quit a project, then we would expect our decisions to quit be correlated with low willpower and blood sugar levels, and hence to be ignored!
It's hard to oppose these issues: humans are [biased](http://lesswrong.com/lw/uu/why_does_power_corrupt/) [hardware](http://lesswrong.com/lw/uv/ends_dont_justify_means_among_humans/). If one doesn't know exactly why a bias is bad, countering a bias may simply [let other biases](http://lesswrong.com/lw/he/knowing_about_biases_can_hurt_people/) [hurt you](http://wiki.lesswrong.com/wiki/Valley_of_bad_rationality). Anecdotally, a number of people have problems with quite the opposite of sunk cost fallacy - overestimating the marginal value of the alternatives and discounting how little further investment is necessary[^sunk-cost-fallacy-fallacy], and people try to commit themselves by deliberately buying things they don't value.[^sunk-commitment] (This seems doubly plausible given the high value of [Conscientiousness](About#fn26)/Grit[^Grit] - with marginal return high enough that it suggests most people do not commit long-term nearly enough, and if sunk cost is the price of reaping those gains...)
[^sunk-cost-fallacy-fallacy]: "Real artists ship", as the saying goes. One might call using sunk cost fallacy on personal projects the ["'sunk cost fallacy' fallacy"](http://lesswrong.com/r/discussion/lw/9jy/sunk_costs_fallacy_fallacy/):
> I have a problem with never finishing things that I want to work on. I get enthusiastic about them for a while, but then find something else to work on. This problem seems to be powered partially by my sunk costs fallacy hooks. When faced with the choice of finishing my current project or starting this shiny new project, my sunk costs hook activates and says "evaluate future expected utility and ignore sunk costs". The new project looks very shiny compared to the old project, enough that it looks like a better thing to work on than the rest of the current project. The trouble is that this always seems to be the case. It seems weird that the awesomeness of my project ideas would have exponential growth over time, so there must be something else here.
[Johnicholas](http://lesswrong.com/lw/55i/failure_modes_sometimes_correspond_to_game/):
> ...Sometimes it can be hard to maintain a good balance among multiple activities. For example, it is important to notice new good ideas. However, I tend to spend too much time pursuing novelty, and not enough time working on the best idea that I've found so far. There is a tradition of browser games (see [Kingdom Of Loathing](!Wikipedia)) that enforce a kind of balance using a virtual currency of 'turns'. You accumulate turns slowly in real time, and essentially every action within the game uses up turns. This enforces not spending too much time playing the game (and increases the perceived value of the game via forced artificial scarcity, of course). If I gave myself 'explore dollars' for doing non-exploration (so-called exploit) tasks, and charged myself for doing exploration tasks (like reading [arXiv](!Wikipedia) or Wikipedia), I could enforce a balance. If I were also prone to the opposite problem ('A few months in the lab can often save whole hours in the library.'), then I might use two currencies; exploring costs explore points but rewards with exploit points, and exploiting costs exploit points but rewards with explore points. (Virtual currencies are ubiquitous in games, and they can be used for many purposes; I expect to find them able to be placed across from many different failure modes.)
[Mass Driver](http://lesswrong.com/lw/2gi/the_instrumental_value_of_your_own_time/):
> ...I have the same problem at work; although, by mainstream society's standards, I am a reasonably successful professional, I can't really sit down and write a great essay when I'm too hot, or, at least, it seems like I would be more productive if I stopped writing for 5 minutes and cranked up the A/C or changed into shorts. An hour later, it seems like I would be more productive if I stopped writing for 20 minutes and ate lunch. Later that afternoon, it seems like I would be more productive if I stopped for a few minutes and read an interesting article on general science. These things happen even in an ideal working environment, when I'm by myself in a place I'm familiar with. If I have coworkers, or if I'm in a new town, there are even more distractions. If I have to learn who to ask for help with learning to use the new software so that I can research the data that I need to write a report, then I might spend 6 hours preparing to spend 1 hour writing a report.
>
> All this worries me for two reasons: (1) I might be failing to actually optimize for my goals if I only spend 10-20% of my time directly performing target actions like 'write essay' or 'kayak with friends', and (2) even if I am successfully optimizing, it sucks that the way to achieve the results that I want is to let my attention dwell on the most efficient ways to, say, brush my teeth. I don't just want to go kayaking, I want to think about kayaking. Thinking about driving to the river seems like a waste of cognitive 'time' to me.
[Daniel Meade](https://plus.google.com/u/0/116594037963311275379/posts/5c1Y78Luymg):
> ...I've had so many 'projects' over the past few years I've lost count. Has any one of them seen the light of day? Well yes, but that failed miserably. The point is, it's all too easy to get distracted and move onto something else, perhaps it's that hurdle where you're just not sure what to do next or how to do it, so instead of finding a way to tackle it head on, you take the easy way out and start something new. I'm quick to blame my failings on the lack of capital, that I '*need*' to get my projects off the ground. And that justifies my avoidance. Of course, it doesn't, far from it. But I just don't know how to push through, not right now any way.
We all have heard of businesses engaged in sunk cost, but that doesn't tell us anything unless we know to what degree, if any, they engage in the opposite behavior, switching *too much*; from ["How DigiCash Blew Everything"](http://cryptome.org/jya/digicrash.htm), _Next! Magazine_:
> It all started out quite nicely. The brand new company sold a smart card for closed systems which was a cash-cow for years. It was at this time that the first irritants appeared. Even if you are a brilliant scientist, that doesn't mean you are a good manager. [David Chaum](!Wikipedia) was a control freak, someone who couldn't delegate anything to anyone else, and insisted upon watching over everybody's shoulders. "That resulted in slowing down research," explains an ex-[DigiCash](!Wikipedia) employee who wished to remain anonymous. "We had a lot of half-finished product. He continuously changed his mind about where things were headed."
[^optimism]: [Dil Green](http://lesswrong.com/lw/jg/planning_fallacy/2s2y)'s description:
> - 'tactical optimism' : David Bohm's term for the way in which humans overcome the (so far) inescapable assessment that; 'in the long run, we're all dead'. Specifically, within the building industry, rife with non-optimal ingrained conditions, you wouldn't come to work if you weren't an optimist. Builders who cease to have an optimistic outlook go and find other things to do.
It's hard not to think of Arkes & Hutzel 2000, ["The Role of Probability of Success Estimates in the Sunk Cost Effect"](http://commonsenseatheism.com/wp-content/uploads/2011/09/Arkes-Hutzel-The-role-of-probability-of-success-estimates-in-the-sunk-cost-effect.pdf)
> The sunk cost effect is manifested in a tendency to continue an endeavor once an investment has been made. Arkes and Blumer (1985) showed that a sunk cost increases one's estimated probability that the endeavor will succeed [ p(_s_)]. Is this p(_s_) increase a cause of the sunk cost effect, a consequence of the effect, or both? In Experiment 1 participants read a scenario in which a sunk cost was or was not present. Half of each group read what the precise p(_s_) of the project would be, thereby discouraging p(s) inflation. Nevertheless these participants manifested the sunk cost effect, suggesting p(_s_) inflation is not necessary for the effect to occur. In Experiment 2 participants gave p(_s_) estimates before or after the investment decision. The latter group manifested higher p(_s_), suggesting that the inflated estimate is a consequence of the decision to invest.
[^hyperbolic-oppose]: The reasoning goes [like this](http://lesswrong.com/lw/at/sunk_cost_fallacy/72v):
> Another reason for honoring the sunk cost of the movie ticket (related to avoiding regret) is that you know yourself well enough to realize you often make mistakes. There are many irrational reasons why you would not want to see the movie after all. Maybe you're unwilling to get up and go to the movie because you feel a little tired after eating too much. Maybe a friend who has already seen the movie discourages you to go, even though you know your tastes in movies don't always match. Maybe you're a little depressed and distracted by work/relationship/whatever problems. Etc.
>
> For whatever reason, your past self chose to buy the ticket, and your present self does not want to see the movie. Your present self has more information. But this extra information is of dubious quality, and is not always relevant to the decision. But it still influences your state of mind, and you know that. How do you know which self is right? You don't, until after you've seen the movie. The marginal costs, in terms of mental discomfort, of seeing the movie and not liking it, are usually smaller than the marginal benefit of staying home and thinking about what a great movie it could have been. The reasoning behind this trivial example can easily be adapted to sunk cost choices in situations that do matter.
[And again](http://lesswrong.com/lw/at/sunk_cost_fallacy/781):
> People who take into account sunken costs in *everyday decisions* will make better decisions on average. My argument relies on the proposition that a person's estimate of his own utility function is highly noisy. In other words, you don't really know if going to the movie will make you happy or not, until you actually do it.
>
> So if you're in this movie-going situation, then you have at least two pieces of data. Your current self has produced an estimate that says the utility of going to the movie is negative. But your *former* self produced an estimate that says the utility is substantially positive - enough so that he was willing to fork over $10. So maybe you average out the estimates: if you currently value the movie at -$5, then the average value is still positive and you should go. The real question is how confident you are in your current estimate, and whether that confidence is justified by real new information.
[^sunk-commitment]: Initiation rituals may increase commitment as they become more unpleasant or demanding ([Aronson & Mills 1959](http://tino-design.com/tino-design/Documents/Elio2/psych/Dissertation/Elio%20and%20nat,%20social,%20millitary/aronson%20and%20mills,%201959.pdf "The effect of severity of initiation on liking for a group")); and we can see attempts in our daily lives with consumerism - buying gym memberships or exercise equipment; McAfee et al 2007:
> Anecdotal evidence suggests that individuals may even exploit their own reactions to sunk expenditures to their advantage. [Steele (1996, p. 610)](/docs/sunkcosts/1996-steele.pdf "Nozick on Sunk Costs") [cf. Elster 2000, [_Ulysses Unbound: Studies in Rationality, Precommitment and Constraints_](http://www.amazon.com/Ulysses-Unbound-Rationality-Precommitment-Constraints/dp/0521665612/), and [Kelly 2004](https://www.princeton.edu/~tkelly/sc.pdf "Sunk Costs, Rationality, and Acting For the Sake of the Past")] and [Walton (2002, p. 479)](http://www.dougwalton.ca/papers%20in%20pdf/02sunkcosts.pdf "The Sunk Cost Fallacy or Argument from Waste") recount stories of individuals who buy exercise machines or gym memberships that cost in the thousands of dollars, even though they are reluctant to spend this much money, reasoning that if they do, it will make them exercise, which is good for their health. A reaction to sunk costs that assists in commitment is often helpful.
Or prepaying for lessons, or buying excessively expensive [writing tools](http://hackerne.ws/item?id=740924):
>> 'Are [Moleskines](!Wikipedia) really worth the cost compared to Mead? If so, why?'
>
> Plenty of people seem to swear by them. But here's the thing - it's not so much the cost (in absolute sums, it's not that large). It's whether you use it. You obviously sweat over costs; perhaps this sweating can be a cudgel to force you to write down whatever. The more a moleskine isn't worth buying, the more you will find yourself compelled to use it. Then wouldn't you be better off in the end?
[Geoffrey Miller](!Wikipedia "Geoffrey Miller (psychologist)") mocks this logic (pg 122 of [_Spent_](http://www.amazon.com/Spent-Sex-Evolution-Consumer-Behavior/dp/0143117238/) 2011):
> All experienced fitness machine salespeople are well aware that this is the fate of most of their products. What they are really selling consumers is the delusion that the sunk costs of buying the machines will force them to exercise conscientiously. (The consumers know that they could have already been jogging for months around their neighborhood parks in their old running shoes, but they also know that their access to the parks and shoes has not, empirically, been sufficient to induce regular exercise.) So, the consumer thinks: 'If I invest $3,900 in this PreCor EFX5.33 elliptical trainer, it will (1) call forth regular aerobic activity from my flawed and unworthy body, through the techno-fetishistic magic of its build quality, and (2) save me money in the long run by reducing medical expenses.' The salesperson meanwhile thinks: '20% commission!' and the manufacturer thinks: 'We can safely offer a ten-year warranty; because the average machine only gets used seventeen times in the first two months after purchase.' Everybody's happy, except for most consumers, and they don't complain because they think it's all their fault that they're failing to use the machine.' The few conscientious consumers who do use the equipment regularly enjoy many benefits: efficient muscle building and fat burning through the low perceived exertion of the PreCor's smooth elliptical movement; a lean body that elicits lust and respect; a self-satisfied glow of moral superiority.
[^Grit]: Grit is a toughed narrower version of [Conscientiousness](!Wikipedia "Conscientiousness#Personality models"); from ["Grit: Perseverance and Passion for Long-Term Goals"](http://www.sas.upenn.edu/~duckwort/images/Grit%20JPSP.pdf):
> ...We define grit as perseverance and passion for long-term goals. Grit entails working strenuously toward challenges, maintaining effort and interest over years despite failure, adversity, and plateaus in progress. The gritty individual approaches achievement as a marathon; his or her advantage is stamina. Whereas disappointment or boredom signals to others that it is time to change trajectory and cut losses, the gritty individual stays the course. Our hypothesis that grit is essential to high achievement evolved during interviews with professionals in investment banking, painting, journalism, academia, medicine, and law. Asked what quality distinguishes star performers in their respective fields, these individuals cited grit or a close synonym as often as talent. In fact, many were awed by the achievements of peers who did not at first seem as gifted as others but whose sustained commitment to their ambitions was exceptional. Likewise, many noted with surprise that prodigiously gifted peers did not end up in the upper echelons of their field.
>
> More than 100 years prior to our work on grit, Galton (1892) collected biographical information on eminent judges, statesmen, scientists, poets, musicians, painters, wrestlers, and others. Ability alone, he concluded, did not bring about success in any field. Rather, he believed high achievers to be triply blessed by 'ability combined with zeal and with capacity for hard labour' (p. 33). Similar conclusions were reached by Cox (1926) in an analysis of the biographies of 301 eminent creators and leaders drawn from a larger sample compiled by J. M. Cattell (1903). Estimated IQ and Cattell's rank order of eminence were only moderately related (r=ϭ.16) when reliability of data was controlled for. Rating geniuses on 67 character traits derived from Webb (1915), Cox concluded that holding constant estimated IQ, the following traits evident in childhood predicted lifetime achievement: 'persistence of motive and effort, confidence in their abilities, and great strength or force of character' (p. 218).
>
> ...However, in the Terman longitudinal study of mentally gifted children, the most accomplished men were only 5 points higher in IQ than the least accomplished men (Terman & Oden, 1947). To be sure, restriction on range of IQ partly accounted for the slightness of this gap, but there was sufficient variance in IQ (SD ϭ 10.6, compared with SD ϭ 16 in the general population) in the sample to have expected a much greater difference. More predictive than IQ of whether a mentally gifted Terman subject grew up to be an accomplished professor, lawyer, or doctor were particular noncognitive qualities: 'Perseverance, Self-Confidence, and Integration toward goals' (Terman & Oden, 1947, p. 351). Terman and Oden, who were close collaborators of Cox, encouraged further inquiry into why intelligence does not always translate into achievement: 'Why this is so, what circumstances affect the fruition of human talent, are questions of such transcendent importance that they should be investigated by every method that promises the slightest reduction of our present ignorance' (p. 352).
>
> Reviewing the biographical details of Darwin, Einstein, and other geniuses, Howe (1999) disputed the assumption that high achievement derives directly from exceptional mental ability: 'Perseverance is at least as crucial as intelligence. . . . The most crucial inherent differences may be ones of temperament rather than of intellect as such' (p. 15). Likewise, summarizing an extensive body of research on the development of expertise, Ericsson and Charness (1994) concluded that in chess, sports, music, and the visual arts, over 10 years of daily 'deliberate practice' set apart expert performers from less proficient peers and that 20 years of dedicated practice was an even more reliable predictor of world-class achievement. Like Howe, Ericsson and Charness suggested that inborn ability is less important than commonly thought: 'More plausible loci of individual differences are factors that predispose individuals toward engaging in deliberate practice and enable them to sustain high levels of practice for many years' (p. 744).
>
> ...The cross-sectional design of Study 1 limits our ability to draw strong causal inferences about the observed positive association between grit and age. Our intuition is that grit grows with age and that one learns from experience that quitting plans, shifting goals, and starting over repeatedly are not good strategies for success. In fact, a strong desire for novelty and a low threshold for frustration may be adaptive earlier in life: Moving on from dead-end pursuits is essential to the discovery of more promising paths. However, as Ericsson and Charness (1994) demonstrated, excellence takes time, and discovery must at some point give way to development. Alternatively, McCrae et al. (1999) speculated that maturational changes in personality, at least through middle adulthood, might be genetically programmed. From an evolutionary psychology perspective, certain traits may not be as beneficial when seeking mates as when providing for and raising a family. A third possibility is that the observed association between grit and age is a consequence of cohort effects. It may be that each successive generation of Americans, for social and cultural reasons, has grown up less gritty than the one before (cf. Twenge, Zhang, & Im, 2004).
# Thoughtlessness: the real bias
One of the known ways to eliminate sunk cost bias is to be explicit and emphasize the costs of continuing ([Northcraft and Neale, 1986](/docs/sunkcosts/1986-northcraft.pdf), [Tan and Yates, 1995](/docs/sunkcosts/1995-tan.pdf), Brockner et al 1982[^Brockner-1982] & conversely Brockner 1981[^Brockner-1981], McCain 1986), as well as setting explicit budgets ([Simonson & Staw 1992](/docs/sunkcosts/1992-simonson.pdf "De-escalation strategies: A comparison of techniques for reducing commitment to losing courses of action"), [Heath 1995](http://faculty-gsb.stanford.edu/heath/documents/escalationanddeescalation.pdf "Escalation and de-escalation of commitment in response to sunk costs")^[Heath takes the use of 'budget accounting' - which can obviously lead to reduced total return, as it did for subjects in his experiments, who if they stuck it out and escalated commitments earned $7.35 versus the budget-users at $4.84 - as often conflicting with normative standards. My own perspective is to wonder how much budget making resembles writing down one's justification for a particular probabilistic prediction, [a strategy which reduces hindsight bias](/docs/sunkcosts/1988-arkes.pdf "'Eliminating the hindsight bias', Arkes et al 1988") when one's predictions are ultimately falsified.], [Boulding et al 1997](/docs/sunkcosts/1997-boulding.pdf "Pulling the Plug to Stop the New Product Drain")). Fancy tools don't add much effectiveness^[See, for example, [Pala et al 2007](http://www.systemdynamics.org/conferences/2007/proceed/papers/PALA404.pdf "Effects of causal loop diagrams on escalating commitment") which investigated whether [causal loop diagrams](!Wikipedia) helped people prevent sunk cost more than being given "a list of important factors". They didn't.] This, combined with the previous learning-based theory of sunk cost, suggests something to me.
[^Brockner-1981]: ["Face-saving and entrapment"](/docs/sunkcosts/1981-brockner.pdf), Brockner 1981:
> Entrapping conflicts are those in which individuals: (1) have made substantial, unrealized investments in pursuit of some goal, and (2) feel compelled to justify these expenditures with continued investments, even if the likelihood of goal attainment is low. It was hypothesized that entrapment (i.e., amount invested) would be influenced by the relative importance individuals attach to the costs and rewards associated with continued investments. Two experiments tested the notion that entrapment would be more pronounced when costs were rendered less important (and/or rewards were made more important). In Experiment 1, half of the subjects were instructed beforehand of the virtues of investing conservatively (Cautious condition), whereas half were informed of the advantages of investing a considerable amount (Risky condition). Investments were more than twice as great in the Risky condition. Moreover, consistent with a face-saving analysis, (1) the instructions had a greater effect on subjects with high rather than low social anxiety, and (2) individuals with high social anxiety who participated in front of a large audience were more influenced by the instructions than were individuals with low social anxiety who participated in front of a small audience. In the second experiment, the importance of costs and rewards were varied in a 2 × 2 design. As predicted, subjects invested significantly more when cost importance was low rather than high. Contrary to expectation, reward importance had no effect. Questionnaire data from this study also suggested that entrapment was at least partially mediated by the participants' concern over the way they thought they would be evaluated. Theoretical implications are discussed.
Disagreeing with Brockner 1981 on the social concern part; ["Factors Affecting Entrapment: Justification Needs, Face Concerns, and Personal Networks"](http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1087332), Karavanov & Cai 2007:
> The current investigation did not support the findings from previous studies that suggest that justification processes and face concerns lead to entrapment. This study found that only internal self-justification and other-positive face concerns are related to entrapment, but instead of contributing to entrapment, these aspects prevent individuals from becoming entrapped. Personal networks were demonstrated to have positive effect on both self- and other-positive face concerns, providing empirical support for the value of using personal networks as a predictor of face goals. However, personal networks did not contribute to entrapment.
[^Brockner-1982]: ["Factors Affecting Entrapment in Escalating Conflicts: The Importance of Timing"](/docs/sunkcosts/1982-brockner.pdf), Brockner et al 1982
> All subjects were given an initial monetary stake and had the opportunity to win more by taking part in an entrapping investment situation. In Experiment 1, half the subjects were provided with a payoff chart that made salient the costs associated with investing (High-cost salience condition) whereas half were not (Low-cost salience condition). Moreover, for half of the subjects the payoff chart was introduced before they were asked to invest (Early condition) whereas for the other half it was introduced after they had invested a considerable portion of their resources (Late condition). Entrapment was lower in the High salience-Early than in the Low Salience-Early condition. However, there was no difference between groups in the Late condition. In Experiment 2, the perceived presence of an audience interacted with personality variables related to face-saving to effect entrapment. When the audience was described as 'experts in decision making,' subjects high in public self-consciousness (or social anxiety) became less entrapped than those low on these dimensions. When the audience consisted of individuals who 'wished simply to observe the experimental procedure,' however, high public self-consciousness (or social anxiety) individuals were significantly more entrapped than lows. Moreover, these interaction effects occurred when the audience was introduced late, but not early, into the entrapment situation. Taken together, these (and other) findings suggest that economic factors are more influential determinants of behavior in the earlier stages of an entrapping conflict, whereas face-saving variables are more potent in the later phases.
>
> ...For example, individuals may 'throw good money after bad' in repairing an old car, remain for an excessively long period of time in unsatisfying jobs or romantic relationships, or decide to escalate the arms race (even in the face of information suggesting the impracticality of all these actions) because of their belief that they have 'too much invested to quit' (Teger, 1980).
I think apparent instances of 'sunk cost' are better described as *thoughtlessness*. To give an example: when chess or [Go](!Wikipedia "Go (game)") players continue throwing pieces into a doomed position, is that because they explicitly realize it is doomed but feel they must persevere *anyway*, or is it due to the fact that chess amateurs commit more [confirmation bias](!Wikipedia)[^falsification] than masters ([Cowley & Byrne 2004](http://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/download?doi=10.1.1.117.8670&rep=rep1&type=pdf "'Chess Masters' Hypothesis Testing'")) and don't realize that the positions are in fact irretrievable? When one engages in spring-cleaning, one may wind up throwing or giving away a great many things which one has owned for months or years but had not disposed of before; is this an instance of *sunk cost* where you over-valued them simply because you have invested into holding onto them for _X_ months, an instance of [endowment effect](!Wikipedia) where it is more valuable because it's yours (a bias which doesn't change with additional investment) - or is this an instance of you simply never before devoting a few seconds to pondering whether you genuinely liked that checkered scarf? When we see an apparent sunk cost, might we not be seeing a well-developed [*habit*](!Wikipedia "Habit (psychology)") which made sense when it was developed and perhaps has simply never been critically re-examined in the light of current circumstances? Habits are invaluable, but they are also invisible and indurate except at times of crisis where one is re-prioritizing things[^NY-Times]
[^falsification]: Not falsifying one's own beliefs or moves is the natural habit of humans, and real effort is reserved for beliefs of other people and especially enemies - simply imaging that one's belief is held by an imaginary friend aids falsification! See Cowley & Byrne 2005, ["When Falsification is the Only Path to Truth
"](http://www.tara.tcd.ie/bitstream/2262/39430/1/When%20Falsification%20is%20the%20Only%20Path%20to%20Truth.pdf); for extensive background on the theory that reason is principally about arguing & persuasion, see Mercier & Sperber 2010's ["Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory"](http://www.dan.sperber.fr/wp-content/uploads/2009/10/MercierSperberWhydohumansreason.pdf).
[^NY-Times]: An interesting example is afforded by the _NY Times_'s ["How Companies Learn Your Secrets"](http://www.nytimes.com/2012/02/19/magazine/shopping-habits.html?pagewanted=all):
> ...two colleagues from the marketing department stopped by his desk to ask an odd question: "If we wanted to figure out if a customer is pregnant, even if she didn't want us to know, can you do that? " As the marketers explained to Pole - and as Pole later explained to me, back when we were still speaking and before Target told him to stop - new parents are a retailer's holy grail. Most shoppers don't buy everything they need at one store. Instead, they buy groceries at the grocery store and toys at the toy store, and they visit Target only when they need certain items they associate with Target - cleaning supplies, say, or new socks or a six-month supply of toilet paper. But Target sells everything from milk to stuffed animals to lawn furniture to electronics, so one of the company's primary goals is convincing customers that the only store they need is Target. But it's a tough message to get across, even with the most ingenious ad campaigns, because once consumers' shopping habits are ingrained, it's incredibly difficult to change them. There are, however, some brief periods in a person's life when old routines fall apart and buying habits are suddenly in flux. One of those moments - *the* moment, really - is right around the birth of a child, when parents are exhausted and overwhelmed and their shopping patterns and brand loyalties are up for grabs. But as Target's marketers explained to Pole, timing is everything. Because birth records are usually public, the moment a couple have a new baby, they are almost instantaneously barraged with offers and incentives and advertisements from all sorts of companies. Which means that the key is to reach them earlier, before any other retailers know a baby is on the way. Specifically, the marketers said they wanted to send specially designed ads to women in their second trimester, which is when most expectant mothers begin buying all sorts of new things, like prenatal vitamins and maternity clothing. "Can you give us a list?" the marketers asked. "We knew that if we could identify them in their second trimester, there's a good chance we could capture them for years," Pole told me. "As soon as we get them buying diapers from us, they're going to start buying everything else too. If you're rushing through the store, looking for bottles, and you pass orange juice, you'll grab a carton. Oh, and there's that new DVD I want. Soon, you'll be buying cereal and paper towels from us, and keep coming back."...As the ability to analyze data has grown more and more fine-grained, the push to understand how daily habits influence our decisions has become one of the most exciting topics in clinical research, even though most of us are hardly aware those patterns exist. One study from Duke University estimated that habits, rather than conscious decision-making, shape 45% of the choices we make every day, and recent discoveries have begun to change everything from the way we think about dieting to how doctors conceive treatments for anxiety, depression and addictions.
Habits are literally thoughtless:
> ...The first time a rat was placed in the maze, it would usually wander slowly up and down the center aisle after the barrier slid away, sniffing in corners and scratching at walls. It appeared to smell the chocolate but couldn't figure out how to find it. There was no discernible pattern in the rat's meanderings and no indication it was working hard to find the treat. The probes in the rats' heads, however, told a different story. While each animal wandered through the maze, its brain was working furiously. Every time a rat sniffed the air or scratched a wall, the neurosensors inside the animal's head exploded with activity. As the scientists repeated the experiment, again and again, the rats eventually stopped sniffing corners and making wrong turns and began to zip through the maze with more and more speed. And within their brains, something unexpected occurred: as each rat learned how to complete the maze more quickly, its mental activity *decreased*. As the path became more and more automatic - as it became a habit - the rats started thinking less and less. This process, in which the brain converts a sequence of actions into an automatic routine, is called "[chunking](!Wikipedia "Chunking (psychology)")." There are dozens, if not hundreds, of behavioral chunks we rely on every day. Some are simple: you automatically put toothpaste on your toothbrush before sticking it in your mouth. Some, like making the kids' lunch, are a little more complex. Still others are so complicated that it's remarkable to realize that a habit could have emerged at all...What Graybiel and her colleagues found was that, as the ability to navigate the maze became habitual, there were two spikes in the rats' brain activity - once at the beginning of the maze, when the rat heard the click right before the barrier slid away, and once at the end, when the rat found the chocolate. Those spikes show when the rats' brains were fully engaged, and the dip in neural activity between the spikes showed when the habit took over. From behind the partition, the rat wasn't sure what waited on the other side, until it heard the click, which it had come to associate with the maze. Once it heard that sound, it knew to use the "maze habit," and its brain activity decreased. Then at the end of the routine, when the reward appeared, the brain shook itself awake again and the chocolate signaled to the rat that this particular habit was worth remembering, and the neurological pathway was carved that much deeper.
# Further reading
- [Escalation of Commitment Behaviour: a critical, prescriptive historiography](http://curve.coventry.ac.uk/open/items/4a1d1bfe-f361-4f8f-3fdd-132444afcaf8/1/ricecomb1.pdf); Rice 2010, PhD thesis
# External links
- [LessWrong discussion](http://lesswrong.com/lw/9si/is_sunk_cost_fallacy_a_fallacy/#comments)
- ["Just Lose Hope Already"](http://lesswrong.com/r/all/lw/gx/just_lose_hope_already/)
- ["What You Should Know About Megaprojects and Why: An Overview"](http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2424835), Flyvbjerg 2014
<!--
# Hyperbolic discounting
[Against Discount Rates](http://lesswrong.com/lw/n2/against_discount_rates/)
http://www.ir.canterbury.ac.nz/bitstream/10092/5414/1/12632743_1129.pdf
Hyperbolic discounting provides the basis for many purported behavioural biases: individuals will too-heavily weigh the present relative to the near or distant future. Some researchers label such behaviour as irrational.9 But while laboratory evidence exists for hyperbolic discounting in particular settings, Anderson et al (2010) find no evidence of substantial hyperbolically discounting behaviour in a field experiment involving a wide sample of adult Danes. Findings of hyperbolic discounting may be fragile to choice of experimental subjects and laboratory settings. Levitt and List (2007) similarly urge caution in extrapolating from economic laboratory results to real world settings.
http://www.dur.ac.uk/resources/dbs/faculty/working-papers/WP2011-01--DiscountingBehavior.pdf "Discounting Behavior and the Magnitude Effect"
Levitt, Stephen D., and John A. List. 2007. 'What do laboratory experiments measuring social preferences reveal about the real world?' Journal of Economic Perspectives, 21:2 (Spring), pp. 153-74.
Rizzo and Whitman (2007) survey the literature asserting policy consequence of irrational hyperbolic discounting. Note that Rasmusen (2008) and Farmer and Geanakoplos (2009) warn that hyperbolic discounting can be consistent with rationality
- Ainslie, G. and Herrnstein, R. (1981). ["Preference reversal and delayed reinforcement"](http://picoeconomics.org/Articles/PrefRevHerrn81.pdf), _Animal Learning Behavior_ 9(4), 476-482. (hyperbolic discounting in pigeons)
Hyperbolic discounting has a biological basis in circadian rhythms?
- ["Positive Temporal Dependence of the Biological Clock Implies Hyperbolic Discounting"](http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3031993/)
- ["Hyperbolic Discounting Emerges from the Scalar Property of Interval Timing"](http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3112317/)
Hyperbolic discounting doesn't exist in practice? ["Discounting Behavior: A Reconsideration"](http://www.dur.ac.uk/resources/dbs/faculty/working-papers/WP2011-01--DiscountingBehavior.pdf) by Steffen Andersen, Glenn W. Harrison, Morten Lau & E. Elisabet Rutström, January 2011
> The implied econometrics calls for structural estimation of the theoretical models, allowing for joint estimation of utility functions and discounting functions. Using data collected from a representative sample of 413 adult Danes in 2009, we draw striking conclusions. Assuming an exponential discounting model we estimate discount rates to be 5.6% on average: this is significantly lower than all previous estimates using controlled experiments. We also find no evidence to support quasi-hyperbolic discounting or 'fixed cost' discounting, and only modest evidence to support other specifications of non-constant discounting. Furthermore, the evidence for non-constant discounting, while statistically significant, is not economically significant in terms of the size of the estimated discount rates. We undertake extensive robustness checks on these findings, including a detailed review of the previous, comparable literature.
>
> ...We do find evidence in favor of flexible Hyperbolic specifications and other nonstandard specifications, but with very modest variations in discount rates compared to those often assumed. We find that a significant portion of the Danish population uses Exponential discounting, even if it is not the single model that best explains observed behavior.
>
> Given the contrary nature of our findings, in terms of the received empirical wisdom, section 6 contains a systematic cataloguing of the samples, experimental procedures, and econometric procedures of the alleged evidence for Quasi-Hyperbolic and non-constant discounting. We conclude that the evidence needed reconsideration. The one clear pattern to emerge from the received literature is that non-constant discounting occurs for some university student samples.
>
> One major robustness check is therefore to see if the disappointing showing for the Quasi-Hyperbolic model is attributable to our population being the entire adult Danish population, rather than university students. Although it is apparent that the wider population is typically of greater interest, virtually all prior experimental evidence that we give credence to comes from convenience samples of university students. We find that there is indeed a difference in the elicited discount rates with (Danish) university students, and that they exhibit statistically significant evidence of declining discount rates. On the other hand, the size of the discount rates for shorter time horizons is much smaller than the received wisdom suggests.
>
> ...Coller and Williams [1999] were the first to demonstrate the effect of a front end delay; their estimates show a drop in elicited discount rates over money of just over 30 percentage points from an average 71% with no front end delay.11 Using the same experimental and econometric methods, and with all choices having a front end delay, Harrison, Lau and Williams [2002] estimated average discount rates over money of 28.1% for the adult Danish population. Andersen, Harrison, Lau and Rutström [2008a] were the first to demonstrate the effect of correcting for non-linear utility; their estimates show a drop in elicited discount rates of 15.1 percentage points from a discount rate over money of 25.2%. These results would lead us to expect discount rates around 10% with a front end delay, with a significantly higher rate when there is no front end delay.
>
> ...The Exponential discounting model indicates a discount rate of only 5.6%, where all discount rates will be presented on an annualized basis. The 95% confidence interval for this estimate is between 4.1% and 7.0%, so this indicates even lower discount rates than the 10.1% reported by Andersen, Harrison, Lau and Rutström [2008a] for the same population in 2003.25 For comparison, the Exponential discounting model assuming a linear utility function implies an 18.3% discount rate, with a 95% confidence interval between 15.5% and 21.2%, so this is also lower than the estimate for 2003 (25.2%, with a 95% confidence interval between 22.8% and 27.6%). We again conclude that correcting for the non-linearity of the utility function makes a significant quantitative difference to estimated discount rates.
>
> The most striking finding from Table 1, for us, is that there is no Quasi-Hyperbolic discounting. The key parameter, $, is not statistically or economically significantly different from 1, and the parameter * is virtually identical to the estimate from the Exponential discounting model. The p-value on a test of the hypothesis that $=1 has value 0.55, although the 95% confidence interval for $ is enough to see that it is not significantly different from 1.
>
> ...The Weibull discounting model in panel F allows a very different pattern of non-constant discounting. Indeed, these parameter estimates do imply discount rates that vary slightly, from 6.7% for a 1 day horizon, to 6.0% for a 2 week horizon, and then down to 5.1% for a one year horizon. But the 95% confidence intervals on all of these is at least between 3% and 7%, and one cannot reject the Exponential discounting model hypothesis that s=1 (p-value of 0.73).
>
> ...The only demographic covariate to have any statistically significant impact on elicited discount rates is whether the individual is a female. Women have discount rates that are 6.6 percentage points lower than men, and the p-value on this estimated effect of 0.092. In turn, this derives from women being more risk averse: their RRA is 0.294 higher than men, with a p-value on this estimated effect of 0.026. Hence they have a more concave utility function and, by Jensen's inequality applied to (0), have a lower implied discount rate. Looking at total effects instead of marginal effects, men on average have discount rates of 7.4% and women have discount rates of 3.6%, and the difference is statistically significant (p-value = 0.004).
>
> ...Our results were a surprise to us, and the robustness checks reported above did not lead us to qualify that reaction. We fully expected to see much more 'hyperbolicky' behavior when we removed the front end delay, and particularly when that was interacted with not providing the implied interest rates of each choice. We were not wedded to one hyperbolicky specification or the other, and did not expect the exponential model to be completely overwhelmed by the alternatives, but we did expect to see much more non-constant discounting. We therefore examined the literature, and tried to draw some inferences about what might explain the apparent differences in results.
>
> ...[Literature survey] We ignored all hypothetical survey studies, on the grounds that the evidence is overwhelming that there can be huge and systematic hypothetical biases, and it is simply inefficient to repeat those arguments and waste time taking such evidence seriously. [Like prisoners doing a long sentence, and knowing the jokes and arguments of cellmates by heart, we would rather just point to surveys and evaluations of the evidence in Harrison [2006] and Harrison and Rutström [2008b].] We also focused on experiments, rather than econometric inferences from naturally occurring data, because those data are easier to interpret and have generated the conventional wisdom.36 We excluded studies that did not lend themselves to inferring a discount function.37 Finally, we excluded any study that used procedures that were patently not incentive-compatible or that involved deception.38
>
> ...One conclusion that we draw is that virtually all previous evidence of non-constant discounting comes from studies undertaken with students. We therefore conducted a conventional laboratory experiment, described below, using the same procedures as in our (artefactual) field experiment but with students recruited in Copenhagen...In order to determine if the evidence for non-constant discounting, such as it is, derives from the general focus on students samples, we replicated our field experiments with a student sample in Copenhagen recruited using standard methods.39 The experimental tasks were identical, to ensure comparability. Table 7 lists estimates from the student responses of the basic models in Table 1. The background risk attitudes of this sample were virtually identical to those of the adult Danish population.40 The results are clear: we obtain no evidence of quasi-hyperbolic discounting, no evidence of fixed-cost discounting, and no evidence of simple hyperbolic discounting. We do observe some non-constancy of some discount rates with the Weibull discounting specification, although the overall effect of the student sample is not statistically significant, as shown by the p-value of 0.18 on the null hypothesis that the specification is actually Exponential.41
-->
<!-- Walton 2002 http://www.dougwalton.ca/papers%20in%20pdf/02sunkcosts.pdf
Capen (1991) argues that overlooking sunk costs can lead to predictably bad decisions that harm a business. Capen's argument (p. 1423) is that the flaw i n ignoring sunk costs is the failure to consider the market value of a project that may appear diminished or worthless to the owner, but might be perceived as valuable by a potential buyer
Nozick's ticket case 4
If I think it would be good for me to see many plays or attend many concerts this year, and I know that when the evening of the performance arrives I frequently will not feel like rousing myself at that moment to go out, then I can buy tickets to many of these events in advance, even though I know that tickets still will be available at the box office on the evening of the performance. Since I will not want to waste the money I have already spent on the tickets, I will attend more performances than I would if I left the decisions about attendance to each evening. True, I may not use all of these tickets - lethargy may triumph on some evenings - yet I will attend more frequently than if no tickets had been purchased in advance. Knowing all this, I purchase the tickets in advance in order to drive myself to attend.
"This two-sided nature of informal fallacies is also evident in how fallacies are taught in logic. At the introductory level, we warn student about committing certain kinds of common reasoning errors and deceptive tricks called fallacies. But then at a more advanced level, in a course on argumentation theory, we teach the students that the so-called fallacies are based on forms of argumentation that are quite often reasonable (non-fallacious). Then we can go into more complex and subtle considerations of using criteria to determine which instances of use are fallacious and which are not. To introduce too many of these subtle considerations at the introductory level may simply inhibit the students by making them despair of trying to undertake a task that seems (at their level) formidable or even impossible. Even if they can recognize relatively clear cases of common fallacies, this relatively crude skill will help them significantly to avoid some common errors and deceptions."
-->
<!--
O'Brien & Folta 2009:
a recent study by Biyalogorsky et al. (2006) demonstrated that, contrary to many previous explanations of escalation of commitment,1 persistence is not driven by psychological involvement with the original decision. While an involvement effect would suggest that irrational biases are at work, the authors found instead that the only psychological mechanism driving persistence was biased belief updating.
Journal of Marketing, 70, 108-121
Behavioral research has found that individual cognitive biases can be largely attenuated when subjects are motivated to be accurate (Kruglanski, 1980), feel that they will be held accountable for their decisions (Tetlock, 1992), take more time to make their decision (Webster, 1993), or even just by the routines of organizational decision-making (Burgelman, 1996; Tetlock, 2000).
- Kruglanski, A. (1980), 'Lay epistemology process and contents,' Psychological Review, 87, 70-87
- Tetlock, P. E. (1992), 'The impact of accountability on judgment and choice: Toward a social contingency model,' Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 25, 331-376
- Webster, D. (1993), 'Motivated augmentation and reduction of the overattributuion bias,' Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65, 261-271
- Burgelman, R. A. (1996), 'Progress model of strategic business exit: Implications for an evolutionary perspective on strategy,' Strategic Management Journal, 17, 193-214.
- Tetlock, P. E. (2000), 'Cognitive biases and organizational correctives: Do both disease and cure depend on the politics of the beholder?,' Administrative Science Quarterly, 45, 293-326
Previous research (Bowen 1987; Northcraft and Wolf 1984; Whyte 1986) suggests that better information or better-structured information can reduce commitment to a losing course of action
-->
<!--
"Cleaning up the big muddy: a meta-analytic review of the determinants of escalation of commitment", Sleesman et al 2012 /docs/2012-sleesman.pdf
...little effort has been made to systematically investigate these various accounts. Using meta-analysis, we present a comprehensive overview of the many determinants found in the literature, an analysis of the power of different theoretical perspectives, and an examination of the relative efficacy of the various theories.
Escalation has been noted as a prominent feature
of a variety of controversial or outright failed or-
ganizational decisions. Examples include the fi-
nancially mismanaged highway construction proj-
ect in Boston known as the Big Dig (Dahl, 2001), the
badly administered development of the Shoreham
Nuclear Power Plant in New York (Ross & Staw,
1993), the rogue trades of Nick Leeson involving
Barings Bank (Jensen, Conlon, Humphrey, & Moon,
2011), the failed “Taurus” information technology
project for the London Stock Exchange (Drum-
mond, 1996), and various military campaigns (e.g.,
Staw, 1976; the title of Staw’s article borrows from
the 1967 Pete Seeger Vietnam War protest song,
“Waist Deep in the Big Muddy”). Recent United
States government assistance to the financial ser-
vices firm AIG has some of the hallmarks of esca-
lation: an initial commitment of $85 billion in sup-
port grew to $172 billion as new problems arose,
even though the assessment of the Government Ac-
countability Office (GAO, 2009) indicated great un-
certainty as to whether AIG would be able to repay
the government.
-->